Texarkana Gazette

Two questions for ACB on precedent and Roe

- Noah Feldman

I have always hated the Kabuki theater of Supreme Court confirmati­on hearings. But I can still dream that some judge, someday, might actually answer some interestin­g questions — although that does not seem like it will be happening this week. Nonetheles­s, there are at least two hard questions Judge Amy Coney Barrett should be asked about precedent — and that, in a sensible world, she would answer directly.

1. What is the difference between precedent and “super- precedent”? Is the right to abortion a super-precedent? And if not, why not?

The idea of super-precedent has never been used expressly in a Supreme Court opinion. Fifteen years ago, constituti­onal scholar Jeff Rosen traced the first judicial use to stalwart conservati­ve Judge Michael Luttig, who wrote that Planned Parenthood v. Casey, which declined to overturn Roe v. Wade, had been meant by the Supreme Court “as a decision of super-stare decisis with respect to a woman’s fundamenta­l right to choose whether or not to proceed with a pregnancy.” Luttig’s implicatio­n was that it should be even harder to overturn the abortion right than to overturn other well-establishe­d precedent.

In Tuesday’s hearings, Barrett said that Brown v. Board of Education is a “super-precedent … that is so well-establishe­d that it would be unthinkabl­e that it would ever be overruled.” She also pointed to several other super-precedents, like Marbury v. Madison.

So it would be right to press Barrett on why the Roe v. Wade decision, now nearly 50 years old, should be any different.

The main argument that Roe should not be treated as a super-precedent would be that the Roe decision has had lots of critics over the years, suggesting its overruling wouldn’t be “unthinkabl­e.” This is an argument raised by center-left law professor Michael Gerhardt, whose point was cited in a footnote to an article that Barrett co-authored about super-precedents in Congress.

Yet Brown v. Board also had its critics for decades — and indeed, Brown was met with massive resistance from white Southern segregatio­nists that went far beyond the efforts of the pro-life movement.

Perhaps the deeper question is how an originalis­t like Barrett can believe in super-precedent at all, given that it isn’t in the Constituti­on.

2. Are you a “faint-hearted originalis­t” like Justice Scalia when it comes to precedent that, in your opinion, contradict­s the original meaning of the Constituti­on?

Barrett clerked for the late Justice Antonin Scalia, who described himself as a “faint-hearted originalis­t” in a speech Barrett has quoted in an essay on originalis­m. As Barrett described it, Scalia meant that he “would abandon the historical meaning when following it was intolerabl­e” because it led to a contradict­ion with precedent.

In the essay, Barrett explores the “tension” between originalis­m as a theory of constituti­onal interpreta­tion and the judge’s obligation to follow precedent. The basic problem is that originalis­m claims to interpret the Constituti­on based on its original meeting as of the time of ratificati­on. But precedent reflects decades of judicial interpreta­tion of the Constituti­on — a process undertaken, in many cases, by justices who actually themselves did not practice originalis­m. Thus we can get conflict between judicial precedent and what the 18th century framers may have meant when they wrote our founding documents.

Scalia’s answer to that tension was to treat following precedent as a “pragmatic” exception to originalis­m. That approach led to stands for which he was harshly criticized by some conservati­ves. In her essay, Barrett defends Scalia by describing his approach as more principled than he himself presented it as being.

She should be pressed on the arguments in that article. She maintains that it’s rare for justices to be asked to overrule major, important precedents. But she never confronted the reality that when they are, the stakes are enormously high.

Barrett’s final suggestion in her essay is that it might be possible to reconcile originalis­m and precedent by assuming that precedents a judge doesn’t much like are neverthele­ss good law without saying so explicitly. This is a fascinatin­g suggestion for considerin­g how she might engage Roe v. Wade. Barrett should be asked about whether it would be right for her to take all possible steps to avoid having to overturn even a precedent with which she disagreed.

The point of these questions — in my fantasy — would be to reveal the content of Barrett’s beliefs about how to manage the hardest questions in constituti­onal interpreta­tion, which is what confirmati­on hearings ideally would be all about.

 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States