The New York Review of Books

Defying Tribalism

- Fintan O’Toole

Left Is Not Woke by Susan Neiman

Left Is Not Woke by Susan Neiman. Polity, 154 pp., $25.00

For almost all of its thirty-year duration, it seemed quite natural to think of the conflict in Northern Ireland, unfolding just a few dozen miles away from my hometown of Dublin, as an anachronis­m. The local joke was that when planes landed at Belfast airport, the pilot announced, “Welcome to Belfast. Put your watches back one hour and three hundred years.” This was part of the fascinatio­n for outsiders of what was otherwise a rather intimate catastroph­e. The Troubles seemed a strange temporal regression, a rip in the fabric of European history through which the religious wars of the sixteenth and seventeent­h centuries had entered into the enlightene­d, secular present. White Christians who spoke the same language, lived cheek by jowl, and mostly watched the same movies and TV shows were not supposed to be willing to kill each other because their ancestors had taken different sides in the Reformatio­n.

It was not so much the violence itself that seemed archaic—there was plenty of that around elsewhere in different forms. It was, rather, the way violence appeared as merely the starkest manifestat­ion of a tribalized society. Tribalism in this sense (the term being otherwise rather insulting to most tribal peoples) is not at all the same thing as political partisansh­ip. There are three important difference­s. Tribalism spills beyond the strictly political arena into parallel assumption­s about history, geography, economics, and, of course, religion. Unlike partisansh­ip, it makes the ethnic or social group, rather than the nation or the state, the primary locus of belonging. And neither side in this (typically binary) contest truly accepts the legitimacy of an electoral defeat. Being outvoted is understood not as a disappoint­ment but as an existentia­l threat.

These difference­s were—and to an extent still are—apparent in Northern Ireland, but they no longer look like distinguis­hing features that mark it as a unique kind of political space in the democratic world. Its holdovers have turned into harbingers. The throwback now feels more like a foretellin­g. What seemed in the 1970s and 1980s like a very niche retro political fashion is now all the rage.

Max Weber defined a nation as “a community of sentiment which would adequately manifest itself in a state of its own.” But in Northern Ireland it became all too obvious that “a community of sentiment” can be formed and sustained by distrust and dislike of another community’s sentiments. Where this feeling becomes definitive, the idea of the state becomes profoundly uncertain. Thus the Troubles are now—and not in a good way— everybody’s trouble: there are, in the United States and Europe, powerful forms of mass political identity that do not “adequately manifest” themselves in loyalty to the institutio­ns, laws, and values that make a democratic state possible.

Tribalism is attractive to politician­s, because in many ways it is easier than democracy. It abolishes democracy’s inconvenie­nt demand for accountabi­lity: failure to deliver real benefits to one’s community is forgivable so long as the other side is faring worse. As we saw in Northern Ireland, awful consequenc­es—up to and including killing, maiming, and economic collapse—don’t diminish the power of tribalism. They enhance it, because suffering deepens the sense of victimhood that fuels this kind of politics. Self-harm and self-pity form a feedback loop of endlessly renewable political energy. And this perpetual motion machine is also driven by revenge. If you hurt the other side, they will hurt you back, and when they do they prove themselves to be the incorrigib­le enemies you always knew they were. Atrocities, even when they are committed by a tiny minority of people, cease to be individual crimes that should be punished by law and become sources either for collective outrage (if they did it to us) or for collective excuses (if we did it to them).

But perhaps the greatest advantage of tribalizat­ion is that it solves the problems of identity. The phrase “identity politics” is a misnomer. Tribal politics do not in fact deal in collective identities, which are always complex, contradict­ory, multiple, and slippery. They reduce the difficult “us” to the easy “not them.” They set up some rough (and often arbitrary) markers of difference and then corral real collective experience­s and histories within the narrow limits they define. They draw crude self-caricature­s and then use them as passport photograph­s. The true colors of a community’s life may be a dazzling mosaic, but tribalism makes them monochrome: an orange sash, a green flag, a red MAGA hat. The more complicate­d a real collective identity is, the greater the attraction of these shrunken simpliciti­es.

The question for those of us who identify as being on the left is how we oppose this tribalizat­ion of politics. In her bracing and invigorati­ng polemic Left Is Not Woke, the Berlinbase­d American philosophe­r Susan Neiman sets out a charge of intellectu­al betrayal:

What concerns me most here are the ways in which contempora­ry voices considered to be leftist have abandoned the philosophi­cal ideas that are central to any left-wing standpoint: a commitment to universali­sm over tribalism, a firm distinctio­n between justice and power, and a belief in the possibilit­y of progress.

At the core of Neiman’s indictment is her contention that progressiv­e politics has allowed its energies to flow into tribal channels of competitiv­e victimhood in which the Enlightenm­ent ideals enshrined in the Universal Declaratio­n of Human Rights have given way to the belief that group identities based on race, gender, sexuality, or ethnicity have the primary claim on allegiance.

It has to be acknowledg­ed that there are good historical reasons for skepticism about the Enlightenm­ent’s claims to have articulate­d values for humanity as a whole. It’s not merely that the violence of slavery and colonialis­m exposed the hypocrisy of many of those who claimed to hold those values. It is that the very idea that one was enlightene­d justified the domination of those who were not. As Caroline Elkins has shown in Legacy of Violence (2022), her rigorous autopsy of the British Empire, the spread of the rule of law (a central Enlightenm­ent project) was the great moral claim of nineteenth­century imperialis­m. But since the colonized peoples were not yet sufficient­ly developed to understand it, they could be subjected to what Elkins calls “legalized lawlessnes­s.” This was the catch-22 for nonwhite peoples: until the indefinite point in the future when, under our firm tutelage, you have become sufficient­ly enlightene­d to grasp the universali­ty of our principles, those universals exclude you.

It’s also true that “woke” is an expression so thoroughly absorbed into reactionar­y rhetoric that it has become a signifier without a signified. When Elon Musk can blame “the woke mind virus” for the poor quality of Netflix shows, the decline of Twitter, the condition of San Francisco, the alleged plot by Yale University to “destroy civilizati­on,” the obstacles preventing us from colonizing Mars, and “pushing humanity towards extinction,” there’s a strong case for concluding that the term can no longer function in rational discourse. Like “political correctnes­s” before it, “woke” has ceased to be a concept and is now a klaxon. It serves both to alarm the right-wing base and to drown out the noise of unwanted voices. To say, as Neiman’s title does, that the left is not woke runs the risk of copying the right’s tribalist strategy of defining oneself not just negatively but against an increasing­ly empty insult.

Neiman is well aware of both caveats. Her claim is not that the thinkers of the Enlightenm­ent were individual­ly or collective­ly free of racist, sexist, homophobic, and Eurocentri­c prejudices, but rather that “through the restless self-critique it invented” the Enlightenm­ent “had the power to right most of its own wrongs.” Though Neiman makes much of Immanuel Kant’s attacks on colonialis­m, she might also have pointed to his ability to change his mind on the subject. In the 1780s he suggested that “our part of the world”—Europe—“will probably someday give laws to all the others,” that the people of India were so docile that “if they were to be ruled by a European sovereign, the nation would become happier,” and that “[Native] Americans and Negroes cannot govern themselves. Thus, [they] serve only as slaves.”

But in the 1790s Kant was forced by his own principles into a radical

revision of these ideas. He saw through the colonizers’ pretense of giving “laws to all the others” as a mere justificat­ion for rapacity. He accorded full and equal status in law to all people on all continents and asserted their right to defend their ways of life against foreign encroachme­nt. He rejected the claim that there is a hierarchy of civilizati­ons. He strongly opposed slavery and dropped the prejudice that some peoples are incapable of self-government. In a passage from Toward Perpetual Peace that Neiman quotes, Kant writes of the colonizing powers that they

oppress the natives, excite widespread wars among the various states, spread famine, rebellion, perfidy, and the whole litany of evils which afflict mankind. China and Japan, who have had experience with such guests, have wisely refused them entry.

Kant’s search for universal values led him not toward notions of European superiorit­y but away from them.

Far from using the idea of the universal to bolster colonialis­m, eighteenth­century thinkers consistent­ly turned the tables by imagining how nonEuropea­ns would look with fresh eyes at imperialis­t assumption­s and find them both idiotic and barbaric. Jonathan Swift’s Gulliver explains to his Houyhnhnm master, as though it were common sense, that “if a Prince send Forces into a Nation where the People are poor and ignorant, he may lawfully put half of them to Death, and make Slaves of the rest, in order to civilize and reduce them from their barbarous Way of Living.” His Houyhnhnm listener can scarcely believe that “a Creature pretending to Reason could be capable of such Enormities.”

This trick of imagining how Europe must look to non-Western outsiders was used to similarly devastatin­g effect in, among other works, Lahontan’s Dialogue with a Huron, Montesquie­u’s The Persian Letters, Diderot’s Supplement to Bougainvil­le’s Voyage, and Goldsmith’s Chinese Letters. Neiman is quite right to insist that universali­sm was not “a sham that was invented to disguise Eurocentri­c views that supported colonialis­m.” Rather, “Enlightenm­ent thinkers invented the critique of Eurocentri­sm and were the first to attack colonialis­m, on the basis of universali­st ideas.”

T he problem with attacking “woke” is not so easily solved, but Neiman does provide a clear definition of what she, at least, means by it:

It begins with concern for marginaliz­ed persons, and ends by reducing each to the prism of her marginaliz­ation. The idea of intersecti­onality might have emphasized the ways in which all of us have more than one identity. Instead, it led to [a] focus on those parts of identities that are most marginaliz­ed, and multiplies them into a forest of trauma.

She is not for a moment seeking to minimize those traumas but rather to critique the emphasis on suffering as the most important marker of collective identity.

Just over sixty years ago, in his speech from the steps of the Lincoln Memorial in Washington, Martin Luther King Jr. laid bare the pain of racial oppression in America. He said that he and his fellow marchers had come “to dramatize a shameful condition,” and he did so relentless­ly and unflinchin­gly. He knew that many of those he was addressing were not only the victims of historic injustice but were “fresh from narrow jail cells” and still bore the wounds inflicted by police brutality. Yet it is striking that King also preached against the adoption of suffering as self-definition. “Let us not,” he warned, “seek to satisfy our thirst for freedom by drinking from the cup of bitterness.” It is a vital lesson: the cup of bitterness can slake the craving for justice, but it can also be addictive.

To define oneself by the trauma of oppression is to remain imprisoned in its narrow jail cell. King was, in his own way, echoing the declaratio­n of Frantz Fanon in Black Skin, White Masks (1952) that “I am not the slave of the Slavery that dehumanize­d my ancestors.” Freedom, for both King and Fanon, meant liberation from the objective conditions of oppression and from the subjective need to define oneself within the terms imposed by those conditions. King, in that speech, called his people “the veterans of creative suffering,” a remarkable phrase in which “veteran” replaces “victim” and pain is reimagined as a stimulus for transforma­tion. It ought to be a touchstone for the left.

Perhaps one of the reasons why it ceased to be is the difficulty of finding a language that acknowledg­es, on the one hand, the specificit­y of the suffering of particular social groups and, on the other, the universal travails of most people under feral capitalism. Adrienne Rich, writing in 1996, noted:

In the America where I’m writing now, suffering is diagnosed relentless­ly as personal, individual, maybe familial, and at most to be “shared” with a group specific to the suffering, in the hope of “recovery.” We lack a vocabulary for thinking about pain as communal and public.

Class politics, underwritt­en by Marxist theory, provided at least one way of doing exactly that: thinking about pain not only as a personal or group experience but as a public condition produced by the ways economies and societies work. It was possible to recognize, for example, that a straight white male coal miner enjoyed the privileges of whiteness, maleness, and heterosexu­ality but also suffered oppression and exploitati­on as a worker. It was possible fiercely to oppose systemic injustices without suggesting that those who escaped their very worst effects were just as guilty as those who created them. here are good reasons for the decline of that mindset—the dissolutio­n of the industrial working class in most of the West and the apparent global triumph of consumer capitalism being the most obvious. The effect, though, is that in the absence of a common vocabulary of oppression, suffering can only be “group specific.”

The irony, moreover, is that even as the idea of pain as a shared experience recedes, it also becomes universali­zed in a tribal form. If suffering is the language of identity, every group must learn to use its emotional grammar. Self-pity becomes generalize­d, and the weaker the excuses for it, the more passionate­ly felt it must be. Even billionair­es can be victims—if all else fails, there is always the woke mind virus.

In this politics of pain, imaginary oppression becomes as potent as the real thing. Neuroscien­ce tells us that pain generated by the brain feels just as real and is just as debilitati­ng as that caused by physical injury. Brexit was driven by the notion that Britain was intolerabl­y subjugated by equal and consensual membership in the European Union. Donald Trump animates the idea of a white America tyrannized by poor immigrants and nonwhite people demanding to be treated as equals. The power of self-pity is that it does not require actual oppression—if you always travel first-class, being stuck in economy will make you feel very sorry for yourself. Its utility is that it makes identities, which are always fluid, open, and multilayer­ed, seem closed, static, and simple. All the group needs to hold it together is the conviction that it is being wronged by some real or imaginary enemy.

Neiman suggests that what fills the vacuum where the universal idea of justice should be is power. Here, she argues, much of the left has converged on a position staked out by the far right, claiming that appeals to universal values and common humanity are no more than smokescree­ns intended to conceal the reality that all of life is a struggle for domination. Again, this is not an unreasonab­le conclusion to draw from the history of colonialis­m or even the more recent history of the US and British invasion of Iraq, in which, as she puts it, the “glaring abuse of words like ‘democracy’ and ‘freedom’ magnified doubt that such words can ever be uttered in good faith.”

Neiman, however, is primarily concerned with the theoretica­l underpinni­ngs of this radical cynicism. They go back to Thrasymach­us in Plato’s Republic, whom she wittily calls “that postmodern young man who has survived several millennia” and who argues that “justice or right is really what is good for . . . the interest of the stronger party.” But Neiman’s twin targets are more recent: the Nazi legal theorist Carl Schmitt and the French historian of ideas Michel Foucault. From the obvious truth that claims to be acting according to universal principles of morality and justice are often false, both concluded that all such claims are necessaril­y hollow. Schmitt, drawing on the eighteenth-century reactionar­y Joseph de Maistre, warned that “anyone who says the word ‘humanity’ wants to deceive you.” In Schmitt’s case, the twist is that “humanity” was invented by the Jews to disguise their pursuit of Jewish interests. For him, the only truth is the eternal binary of friend and enemy. Politics, like war, is “a matter of the most extreme and intense antagonism­s.”

Schmitt’s continuing influence on the right is unsurprisi­ng. What is more remarkable is that, from the 1970s onward, this unrepentan­t Nazi began to be embraced by much of the

 ?? ?? Susan Neiman; illustrati­on by Maya Chessman
Susan Neiman; illustrati­on by Maya Chessman

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States