AQ: Australian Quarterly

From the Archive: 1931

Party spirit in politics

- PETER BOARD

Wherever there is politics there will be political parties, just as whenever there is debate we find ourselves drawn to taking sides. We are, and always will be, a tribal species. The formation of parties is a necessary (and inevitable) evil – a shorthand for the broad aspiration­s of a community – but it is important to remember that they are in no way fundamenta­l to the formation of government.

The existence of the Liberal and Labor parties are not enshrined anywhere. They could (and arguably should) wane and disappear as they fail to keep up with the will of the electorate – the cyclical renewal of a healthy democracy.

Despite the ‘major' parties bleeding primary votes for yet another election, Australia is caught in a narrative of good and evil, ying and yang, Lib and Lab. Yet constantly framing Australia's system in 2-party-preferred terms only perpetuate­s a myth that harms our nation's health.

The very concept of parties contradict­s the essence of representa­tional democracy, in which constituen­ts are meant to vote for the person most suitable to represent the majority of their needs. Yet no party can represent all the needs of all the people of Australia, resulting in the situation where your representa­tive is required by party policy to vote against your best interests.

One need only think of Michael Mccormack's disastrous response to the question of whether he could think of a single instance where the Nationals had backed farmers over miners…

There is no practical way to be rid of parties in politics, but there is a way to break the thrall of the major parties. We need to recognise that Australian politics is not a two horse race, with the riff-raff having jumped the fence and invaded the track. A renewal of Australia politics will not come from parties that hand the rights of government back and forth between themselves, and that feel born to rule.

In 1931, Australia's federal democracy was still fledgling and the ubiquitous nature of political parties was yet to be fully entrenched. ‘Partyism' was causing the exact same problems as it does today.

This piece from the AQ archives makes for an entertaini­ng read, particular­ly given many of the quotes could have fallen from the lips of a weary, modern-day political boffin. Never mind that they were said almost 90 years ago…

When William III [of England] determined to select his ministers from the dominant party in the House of Commons [in 1698], he created a distinctio­n for future generation­s between politics and statecraft and between the politician and the statesman.

From that time it has been the object of political parties to command the majority of votes in all those parliament­s which follow the constituti­on of the British Parliament and, by so doing, to secure for their adherents the power and the spoils of office. Party politics, like war, has in its operation called out the best and the worst in human nature.

Patriotism and self-abnegation, as well as deceit and self-seeking, have marked the history of political parties, but it is

the latter which has led to the widespread condemnati­on of party politics.

[Edmund] Burke declared, "Parties must ever exist in a free country." Party government, although it has been in operation under the British Constituti­on for nearly 250 years and has borne the distinctiv­e marks we recognise today for nearly 100 years, has undoubtedl­y developed features which are detrimenta­l to the well-being of the

State. Australian instances can readily be found.

Political parties have adopted an organisati­on governed by rules so inflexible that it has acquired the rigidity of a machine. Under the party system the electors have been restricted in their choice of representa­tives by a preselecti­on of candidates in which the members of the party as a whole have had no voice.

These electors are denied the right of choice by the interposit­ion of small groups who, with the "arrogance of elected persons," determine which candidates shall be the favoured recipients of their votes.

Again, political parties have claimed the right to dictate to government­s what their administra­tive and legislativ­e actions shall be, and ministries have been found so subservien­t to this dictation that the responsibi­lity of a ministry to parliament has been discarded and its place taken by the responsibi­lity of ministers to persons outside parliament.

Political parties in the course of their developmen­t, have establishe­d over their own members a tyranny which destroys freedom and independen­ce of thought.

Obviously, membership of a party implies a concurrenc­e in the foundation principles of the party and in the attitude towards public welfare that the party adopts, but outside of that claim for allegiance, where difference­s of opinion may legitimate­ly exist without inconsiste­ncy with party membership, liberty of opinion has been denied and the rulers of the party have adopted the theory stated by Hobbes in his Leviathan that, "A doctrine repugnant to civil society is that whatever a man does against his conscience is sinne."

Further, party politics gives a bias to the administra­tive acts of government which interferes with justice in administra­tion. However perfect an Act of Parliament may be, it touches private and personal interests at some point or other and a vigorous political party on the alert to make party allegiance profitable to its members, takes care that the administra­tor does not so far regard the public welfare that the opportunit­ies for serving these private and personal interests are lost.

Finally, political partyism tends to produce sectional legislatio­n. Representi­ng, as the party does, a section of the people of the State, it feels that the support of that section can only be retained if the legislatio­n the party promotes gives some exclusive privileges to the section which supports it.

If a party rests for its existence on a class-conscious cleavage, it produces a class legislatio­n which disregards the welfare of the whole people, so that government "of the people, for the people, by the people" does actually "perish from the land."

These evils undoubtedl­y do follow from political partyism in government. But the question may well be asked: Are these evils a necessary and inevitable consequenc­e of political parties, or rather are they not inherent in the mechanism, the organisati­on through which effect is given to the party's objects?

These electors are denied the right of choice by the interposit­ion of small groups who, with the "arrogance of elected persons," determine which candidates shall be the favoured recipients of their votes.

There must be parties as long as there are, amongst the people of the State, opposing attitudes on political problems. Parties are distinguis­hed from one another less by their formulated creeds than by their "attitudes towards life, the problems of life, and social forces and humanity."

Where a group of persons finds itself adopting a common attitude on these questions a party comes into existence. It is this community of thought and sentiment that is the essential element of party. But there is nothing in this community of sentiment and attitude that makes necessary or inevitable those evils which are deplored as the results of political parties.

It is when the effort is made to give practical effect to the sentiments which hold the party together that machinery is devised which produces these evils. It then becomes possible that a party which is bound together by a common attitude towards life's problems, which is in every respect admirable, may even counteract its own principles and violate the fundamenta­l requiremen­ts of well-ordered social welfare, by the adoption of a party mechanism which is relentless in its operation.

Is a party so far inseparabl­e from its

Political parties in the course of their developmen­t, have establishe­d over their own members a tyranny which destroys freedom and independen­ce of thought.

Peter Board, 1931

Is a party so far inseparabl­e from its mechanism that it cannot give effect to the principles which determine its creed without inevitably doing violence to the purity of political life?

mechanism that it cannot give effect to the principles which determine its creed without inevitably doing violence to the purity of political life? It is only an extreme pessimist's view of human nature that would admit this to be the case.

One or two of the ill effects of partyism might be examined. The complaint that the working of the party machine in the pre-selection of candidates prevents the free choice of the electors might be obviated by means of a primary ballot.

If all the candidates who offer themselves for election were allowed to go to the poll, a preferenti­al system of voting would go far to ensure that the choice of the electors was expressed. But as many party supporters doubt the efficacy of this system, the holding of a preliminar­y ballot in which all members of the party organisati­on had the opportunit­y to vote would leave no doubt as to the candidate of their choice.

Another objection – that the party demands an allegiance of such an exacting character that individual freedom of opinion is stifled – is one that again arises from the organisati­on and mechanism of party and is not a necessary consequenc­e of the existence of party.

Parties, in order to show their attitude on public questions and to supply a basis for the allegiance of their adherents, adopt platforms and policies which attempt to cover the whole field

of possible legislatio­n. The party must have a creed which constitute­s the spiritual element in its life. A statement of this fundamenta­l creed is necessary.

The great English political parties have no written platform, but the Liberal and Conservati­ve parties are the growth of hundreds of years with traditions handed down from a Whig and Tory ancestry. The spiritual elements of the parties are built into these institutio­ns and need no formal statement.

The political parties of a young country have no such traditions and have to formulate their creeds in written platforms. Absolute unwavering adherence to these formal statements is demanded of all members of the party and, as a consequenc­e, a conflict of loyalties arises, the loyalty of members to their organisati­on conflictin­g with their loyalty to their own conviction­s.

It is obvious that the more numerous the "planks" of the party policy are, the greater are the chances of divergence­s of opinion and the greater the conflict of loyalties likely to arise.

Parties in modern politics have departed from Burke's definition of a party as "a body of men united for promoting by their joint endeavours the national interest upon some particular principle upon which they are all agreed." [Moisey] Ostrogorsk­i, in his "Democracy and [the Organisati­on of ] Political Parties" amplifies this definition by stating that "a party is a special combinatio­n, its basis is agreement on a particular principle and its end is the realisatio­n of an object or objects of public interest."

Both definition­s presume that a party has adherence to one great principle as its basis, this being distinguis­hed from the ends which it is sought to achieve. Partyism, however, has departed from these definition­s by attempting to base its constituti­on on a number of principles. By demanding from its members adherence to all of them, it invites the conflicts which sooner or later lead to internal dissension­s and compel a certain amount of insincerit­y of political profession in order to preserve an appearance of unity.

If, on the other hand, a party platform states nothing than the one or the few broad fundamenta­l principles which express its spirit, and its policy expresses only the means by which it hopes to give practical effect to these principles, the tax upon the allegiance of members is reduced and the need for political insincerit­y is lessened.

Australia today stands at the parting of the ways. The whole political structure is strained to meet an altogether unaccustom­ed crisis, and the cohesion of parties is breaking under the strain.

As the Bishop of Armidale remarks in an impressive article in the last ‘Quarterly', “The temper of our political and social life today may be described as one of bitter mortificat­ion." Has not the occasion arisen for a political party which will have the boldness to affirm a belief in something which will transcend the materialis­m that has marked our political standards in the past?

The confession of a political idealism calls for audacity. But, even now, is there not in the Australian nation a large body of electors who still believe that, behind all our material aims, behind all our search for individual advantage, behind all our strivings for social wellbeing, there stand great spiritual issues which we must recognise, which we must embody in our political creeds, and which must create the atmosphere in which our common-weal can be realised?

We are looking to political parties to give a new point of departure. Must Australia look in vain? Must it be disposed of as visionary and impractica­ble that Australia should possess a political party whose spirit shall not be entangled in its own mechanism, but shall preserve its single-minded integrity even amidst the struggles of parties for political ascendancy?

“…conflicts which sooner or later lead to internal dissension­s and compel a certain amount of insincerit­y of political profession in order to preserve an appearance of unity.

 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Australia