Gulf Today

THE HOUSE HAS A DUTY TO IMPEACH AN ERRING PRESIDENT

- BY CASS SUNSTEIN

Suppose that within the next few months, it becomes clear that President Donald Trump has committed impeachabl­e offences. Does the House of Representa­tives have discretion to decide whether to imp each him? or does the constituti­on require it to do so?

The simplest answer, and the best, is that the Constituti­on requires the House to do so. To avoid political bias, let’s bracket all questions associated with President Trump, put current events to one side, and assume that some future president commits (in the words of the Constituti­on) “Treason, Bribery, or other high crimes and misdemeano­rs .” imagine that he has betrayed his country, in a way that constitute­s treason, or that he has killed or imprisoned journalist­s and political enemies (clearly a high crime and misdemeano­r, and so an impeachabl­e offence).

The Constituti­on says that the House of Representa­tives “shall have the sole Power of Impeachmen­t,” and that the Senate “shall have the sole Power to try all Impeachmen­ts.” In light of the historical background, use of these powers is best regarded as mandatory rather than optional, at least when a president has clearly committed impeachabl­e offences. To the founding generation, the impeachmen­t provisions were essential parts of the Constituti­on. As Virginia’s George Mason put it at the Constituti­onal Convention, “No point is of more importance than that the right of impeachmen­t should be continued.” (It is worth pausing over that sentence.)

The power of impeachmen­t was designed to ensure that our system would be one of self-government. It gave We the People an ultimate weapon in the event that the president violated the principles embodied in the Declaratio­n of Independen­ce: “A Prince, whose character is marked by every act which may DEINE A Tyrant, Is unit to BE THE ruler of a free people.”

For this reason, it is wrong to say, as many now do, that the Constituti­on makes impeachmen­t a political question rather than one of law. On the contrary, the Constituti­on sets out a legal standard, which establishe­s a very high bar, and which forbids impeachmen­t on purely political grounds. At the same time, THE Constituti­on speciies what HAS to happen if the constituti­onal standard is clearly met.

Suppose that the House of Representa­tives were entitled to respond to impeachabl­e offences with a kind of shrug, or with the thought, “he’s doing a great job, so we’ll let it pass,” or with the admission, “sure, he’s a bum, but he’s our bum.” That would make a mockery of the constituti­onal plan. It would allow the project of self-government to collapse.

It Is EXCEEDINGL­Y Dificult to READ THE founding-era debates about impeachmen­t – during the Constituti­onal Convention AND THE ratiicatio­n DEBATES – without concluding that if the president has clearly committed an impeachabl­e offence, the House has a constituti­onal duty to impeach him.

Some people reject this conclusion. In an impressive­ly detailed and highly illuminati­ng book, Laurence Tribe and Joshua Matz invoke the analogy of the criminal prosecutor. Tribe and Matz rightly note that criminal prosecutor­s are entitled to exercise discretion. Even if a criminal offence has been committed, prosecutor­s are allowed to conclude that all things considered, criminal prosecutio­n would not be a good idea.

Tribe and Matz make a plausible argument, but their analogy doesn’t work. Faced with limited budgets and many potential targets, prosecutor­s must exercise their judgment in order to ensure that the awesome power of the criminal law is used appropriat­ely. Its constituti­onal obligation is to protect We the People. It is not entitled to look the other way.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Bahrain