Ottawa Citizen

What Whatcott ruling didn’t say also telling

Where was the part about importance of freedom of speech?

- ANDREW COYNE

The very first line in the Supreme Court’s calamitous decision in the case of Saskatchew­an (Human Rights Commission) v. Whatcott gives a clue to where it is going. “All rights guaranteed under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,” it declares, “are subject to reasonable limitation­s.”

This is a legal truism, but as always it is as important what the court did not say. It did not choose to begin a ruling on an important freedom of speech case with a ringing affirmatio­n of the importance of free speech, or what an extraordin­ary thing it is to place restrictio­ns upon it.

Indeed, in its haste to get on with the limiting, it did not even pause to properly quote the section of the Charter that grants the state such authority. The Charter “guarantees” the rights set out in it, Section 1 declares, “subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrab­ly justified in a free and democratic society.”

The limits don’t just have to be reasonable. They have to be “demonstrab­ly justified.”

Where the court’s view of such limits is expansive and approving, the charter is grudging (“only”) and cautious (“demonstrab­ly”). That’s as it should be. If we accept the bedrock premise of a free society, that government is its servant and not its master, then it is up to the state, always, to ask the citizens’ permission before it intrudes on their liberty, and to prove its necessity: it is never the citizen’s obligation to show why he may remain unmolested. That spirit is lamentably absent from the court’s reasoning.

Well, it gets one thing right. It is not enough, the Court writes, that material such as the flyers distribute­d by William Whatcott, a Saskatoon Christian activist, in contravent­ion of the Saskatchew­an Human Rights Code, is offensive or repugnant. Rather, it must involve some harm to others. But look at how loosely the Court defines “harm.”

The code itself outlaws material that “exposes or tends to expose to hatred” any person or group, on the usual list of prohibited grounds. It is not necessary, that is, to show the material in question actually exposes anyone to hatred — only that it might. The court then upholds the ban on the grounds that the hatred to which individual­s might or might not be exposed might in turn lead others to believe things that might cause them to act in certain unspecifie­d but clearly prejudicia­l ways: it “has the potential to incite or inspire discrimina­tory treatment,” or “risks” doing so, or is “likely” to, or at any rate “can.”

After all, the court reasons, “when people are vilified as blameworth­y or undeservin­g, it is easier to justify discrimina­tory treatment.” Perhaps it is: but does such discrimina­tory treatment in fact result? Can the court draw any causal link between speech that “tends to” expose to hatred, for example among the dozens of people who may have received Whatcott’s fevered tracts, and any actual increase in prejudice, let alone acts of discrimina­tion? No it cannot, and what is more it does not care to.

As it has in the past, the court argues that the state’s inability to demonstrat­e the harmful effects of hate speech, far from weakening its case, only confirms it: it is a sign of the “particular­ly insidious” nature of hate speech that it works its harm in ways not visible to hundreds of human rights investigat­ors. Rather, it is sufficient that “Canadians presume” such hateful expression “may lead to harm.” So: from demonstrab­ly justified to presumably justified.

If the court is inclined to wink at the state’s traditiona­l need to prove its case, it is not so indulgent of the defendant. As anyone who follows the workings of human rights tribunals can attest, they are a strange parody of ordinary criminal courts. Not only is it no defence that the accused had an honest belief in what he said: it is not even a defence that it is factually true. Here, too, the court is at peace. As the decision primly advises, “truth may be used for widely disparate ends.” I cannot quite believe I am reading these words, even now.

There are long passages like this in the ruling, wherein the court reels off, without supporting evidence, the many harmful effects it supposes hate speech is likely to cause. It “opposes the targeted group’s ability to find self-fulfillmen­t.” It “impacts on that group’s ability to respond to the substantiv­e ideas under debate.” It “acts to cut off any path of reply by the group under attack.” It is “an effort to marginaliz­e individual­s” based on their membership in a group, to “silence” their “voice,” and so on.

It might be interestin­g to know whether any of this is true — have Jews, for example, the most persistent target of hate speech through the ages, been “silenced”? — but apparently it does not matter: the government is not required to prove its case is true, and the defendant is not saved if his case is. At one point the court muses that a failure to ban hate speech, in so far as it “silences” the targeted groups, may be “more rather than less damaging to freedom of expression.”

From which we may conclude that any government that relaxed such restrictio­ns would soon find itself condemned by the court — as a threat to free speech.

 ??  ??
 ?? TROY FLEECE / REGINA LEADER-POST ?? William Whatcott, seen in Weyburn, Sask., on Wednesday, called the Supreme Court’s ruling ‘complete rubbish’, and said, ‘I’d rather follow God than seven socialists who wear black robes and think they’re smart.’
TROY FLEECE / REGINA LEADER-POST William Whatcott, seen in Weyburn, Sask., on Wednesday, called the Supreme Court’s ruling ‘complete rubbish’, and said, ‘I’d rather follow God than seven socialists who wear black robes and think they’re smart.’

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Canada