Ottawa Citizen

Debating the merits of an electoral reform referendum

Ending partisan self-interest key to reform, writes Mark Crawford.

- Mark Crawford is an assistant professor of political science at Athabasca University, where he teaches Canadian government and democratic theory.

Opinion is divided on the question of whether Canada should have a national referendum on electoral reform.

Supporters of the idea of a referendum correctly suspect that the Liberal government, and indeed all political parties, are inherently in a conflict of interest and should not be blindly trusted to design the rules by which they are elected. The Liberals’ belated decision to relinquish its majority on the Commons special committee on electoral reform, and its commitment to having a free vote in the House of Commons on the final bill, go only part way toward alleviatin­g this concern. A free vote will still be based on the very distortion of representa­tion that electoral reform is supposed to correct: individual Liberal MPs will have 54 per cent of the seats on the strength of 39.5 per cent of the popular vote; one Green MP will have 0.3 per cent of the votes cast despite representi­ng 3.4 per cent of the electorate.

As well, even if these problems could be addressed adequately so as to assure fairness between political parties, there might still be a conflict of interest, since politician­s as a class will still frame the question, and ultimately decide its answer, without due considerat­ion of how much “non-Ottawashed” citizens may not wish to affirm or support political parties as the primary organizati­ons that mediate the popular will.

Opponents of a referendum also have an impressive list of arguments. It is clear referendum­s polarize opinion instead of forging compromise, as both the Quebec referendum campaigns and the recent United Kingdom vote to leave the European Union have shown. The value of representa­tive democracy is that it can examine all sides of an issue and fashion solutions that serve the interests of the majority while still being acceptable to minorities. The debate over Brexit showed how misinforma­tion and errors of fact (concerning Turkey’s membership and the savings for the National Health Service, for example) could not be corrected in time for the vote, with incalculab­le consequenc­es for the future of the U.K. and of Europe.

The ideal solution, therefore, is one that fully addresses the problems of legitimacy and conflict of interest that a referendum is supposed to solve, while at the same time avoiding, if possible, all the problems of polarizati­on and prevaricat­ion that a referendum is prone to create.

Such sound deliberati­on, suitably scrubbed of partisan self-interest, was both the purpose and the effect of the Citizens’ Assembly on Electoral Reform in British Columbia and Ontario, and the Citizens’ Committee in Quebec. Where those processes went wrong (particular­ly in B.C. and in Ontario) was in keeping those islands of deliberati­ve democracy in splendid isolation from the voters, while letting legislatur­es completely off the hook for the decision. Referendum results reflected both the electorate­s’ lack of familiarit­y with the Citizens’ assemblies and the ability of the ruling parties to tilt the playing field away from change. Legislator­s relied too little on democratic persuasion and too much on 60 per cent voter thresholds and inflexible “take-it-orleave-it” ground rules.

Provinces are supposed to be the laboratori­es for policy. Applying the lessons learned from failed (or partially successful) provincial experiment­s to the current referendum debate, we should create a structure for institutio­nal dialogue between a citizens’ committee on electoral reform and Parliament.

Such a structure could force politician­s to justify their rejection of, or amendments to, a citizens’ initiative, thereby improving the legitimacy and deliberati­ve quality of the bill. The result would be to either reduce the felt need for a referendum (if the process went well and a double majority of politician­s and informed citizens could reach consensus) or to better prepare and inform the electorate if a referendum were needed to adjudicate a fundamenta­l disagreeme­nt between parliament­arians and informed citizens. Even many advocates of proportion­al representa­tion, who fear that the rights of all to have their votes counted equally in Parliament will be trampled by a majority, would be more receptive to a referendum if it were needed to resolve such a conflict.

The upshot is that a referendum is necessary only as a last resort. A citizens’ committee should be struck to conduct parallel deliberati­ons with the House of Commons. If the Commons and the citizens’ committee can’t agree, that impasse can be resolved by a referendum. But if they can agree, a referendum should be deemed unnecessar­y.

A citizens’ committee should be struck to conduct parallel deliberati­ons with the House of Commons. If the Commons and the citizens’ committee can’t agree, that impasse can be resolved by a referendum. — Mark Crawford

 ?? J RATCLIFFE/AFP/GETTY IMAGES, FILE ?? In London last month, protesters decry results of the June 23 Brexit referendum, in which the United Kingdom voted to leave the European Union.
J RATCLIFFE/AFP/GETTY IMAGES, FILE In London last month, protesters decry results of the June 23 Brexit referendum, in which the United Kingdom voted to leave the European Union.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Canada