Mint Hyderabad

The state needs new ways to assert its authority online

Its influence over the digital sphere is reliant on execution by private firms but this isn’t an ideal scenario

- RAHUL MATTHAN

is a partner at Trilegal and the author of ‘The Third Way: India’s Revolution­ary Approach to Data Governance’. His X (formerly Twitter) handle is @matthan.

In 1919, Max Weber delivered a lecture titled “Politics as a Vocation,” in which he argued for the first time that the state has a monopoly over the use of physical force. He was looking for a way to justify the state’s use of force and chose to do so by elevating it to the level of a crucial feature of the social contract.

In those days, authority was manifest through tangible expression­s of control— institutio­ns like the police and military, and coercive constructs like laws and regulation­s. The state’s ability to wield this power came to be seen as essential to the maintenanc­e of public order and necessary for the protection of its people.

Over a century has passed since Weber first presented this thesis in 1919. In that time, our world has so dramatical­ly de-materializ­ed that almost all our interactio­ns today take place within the digital realm. Not only has this fundamenta­lly changed the way individual­s interact with each other, it has given rise to new behaviours, the establishn­ormally ment of new marketplac­es, and the rise of new loci of political power. Given how significan­tly things have changed, it is probably worth evaluating whether or not Weber’s theory still holds true.

Today, our activities in the digital sphere are intermedia­ted by technology platforms—social media applicatio­ns, e-commerce sites and digital media services—all of which are owned by Big Tech companies. To access these platforms, we must give our consent to their terms of service.

These agreements are the modern social contract—the new rules of the digital road that determine exactly what we can or cannot do online.The private players we enter into a social contract with have the power to constrain our interactio­ns in new ways that represent a significan­t variation to the classic Weberian social contract.

As much as the modern digital world has given rise to various benefits, it has also unleashed new forms of violence that can be perpetrate­d on people in ways that were simply not possible in 1919. Today, citizens need protection against a whole host of new crimes—cyberbully­ing, cyberstalk­ing, doxxing, fake news and the like. To safeguard them, the state needs to deploy new forms of violence that are relevant to the digital age.

For instance, one of the more effective ways in which the spread of fake news can be curbed is by deploying algorithmi­c de-amplificat­ion—a process that aims to dampen the virality of an online post by adjusting the priority with which it surfaces in the platform’s feed. Other (blunter) interventi­ons include outright censorship and the de-platformin­g of repeat offenders.

The state depends on private enterprise­s to deploy these new forms of digital violence in tackling those who violate their social contract. These businesses, today, are our last line of defence against the new harms of the digital world.

All of which gives rise to an additional complicati­on.

As long the state retained an exclusive monopoly over violence, it was possible for countries to exercise their monopoly over violence in slightly different ways—based on the political reality of each nation-state. Given that the social contract in a liberal democratic country differs from that in, say, a theocratic state, it could be enforced in slightly different ways in each of these different types of states.

This, however, is not easy to do in the digital context. Technology companies take pains to ensure that their users agree to the same terms of service no matter where they access these services from. As a result, regardless of which country a user may reside in, there is no difference in the terms of the contract she signs. This means that so long as the activities of the individual do not offend the platform’s terms of service, it could resist orders issued by the state that call upon its management to inflict digital violence on the user in order to uphold the political values of the state. Unlike the state, which is accountabl­e to its citizens through a democratic process, private companies are only answerable to their shareholde­rs, who end up imposing their own values on its actions. As a result, government­s find that their ability to influence actions in the digital sphere ends up being constraine­d by the whims of corporate shareholde­rs.

Today, the monopoly over violence stands dispersed across private networks in ways that elude the state’s ability to constrain. If we are looking to reinstate Weber’s philosophy of political control in the modern age, we will need to re-imagine our existing governance structures to adequately take into account new realities of the digital world.

One way to give effect to this might be for government­s to establish the protocols by which all digital services are to be delivered within their sovereign territory. This will allow them to retain control over essential elements of state power while still allowing private enterprise to build out additional services on top of these protocols, extending them as required in response to market demand.

This will allow the state to retain enough control over digital activities for it to be able to enforce domestic legal obligation­s, while still letting society benefit from the innovation that only private enterprise can deliver. To give effect to this approach, the state will need to engage more fully with technology and realize that it takes much more than a monopoly over violence to influence the digital sphere.

 ?? ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from India