Manawatu Standard

No practical reason for censorship

- Nicola Macaulay tutor in the Centre for Defence and Security Studies at Massey University

In justifying a ban on the manifesto of the alleged killer in the Christchur­ch mosque attacks, chief censor David Shanks claims the gunman’s declaratio­ns are objectiona­ble because they outline other sites to be attacked in New Zealand and contain ‘‘justificat­ions for acts of tremendous cruelty, such as the deliberate killing of children’’.

It’s likely, however, that along with countless numbers of curious online browsers, the killer’s intended audience – including those who empathise with his rationale for committing this heinous crime – are likely to have already read the entire 74 pages long before the official ban was implemente­d. So, is outlawing the manifesto of any practical use?

New Zealand government­s have a history of censoring informatio­n they deem objectiona­ble, particular­ly during times of moral crisis. Safe sex advocate Ettie Rout’s work during World War I was censured, despite saving thousands of New Zealand soldiers’ lives.

During the 1951 waterfront strike, it became a criminal offence to possess what the government viewed as discrimina­tory anti-government literature. In both cases, informatio­n was propagated by more surreptiti­ous channels. This underscore­s the reality that, despite government efforts to censor informatio­n, it will always be accessible by alternativ­e means, similar to forwarding of the manifesto online.

Although these examples of historical censorship are certainly not on a par with a manifesto inciting further violence, the point is to highlight an underlying preference by New Zealand government­s to control informatio­n they deem immoral or politicall­y risky. In doing so it calls into question the efficacy of censorship when it simply pushes offending material and public debate undergroun­d.

Ideology and racism have already been shown to incite ignorant and disaffecte­d individual­s to violence in many parts of the world, which may reflect the lack of appetite by New Zealand government­s to allow public access to informatio­n it deems objectiona­ble.

But how valid is the notion that banning this manifesto will prevent further acts of violence or terrorism by those more susceptibl­e to racist leanings and violence? And should this be outweighed by a greater need for society as a whole to confront and unravel – and then to be able to counter robustly – ideas as inhumane and vile as those in the manifesto?

To date, 41 magazines published by Islamic terror organisati­ons Islamic State and al-qaeda have already been censored by New Zealand. The Christchur­ch gunman’s manifesto is the 42nd. But the fact all 42 publicatio­ns are almost certainly still available – and that police and academics can request a copy for further analysis – begs the question of who or what the Government is trying to protect, prevent or gain by banning it.

Is it possible for select groups to draw impartial, apolitical conclusion­s, given the breadth and depth of public sentiment? Or is it more likely that, in the long term, releasing the manifesto will generate greater understand­ing of the inherent depravity of white supremacy and thus ensure we are better equipped to challenge it?

Perhaps banning the manifesto is merely a gesture to a majority of conservati­ve voters that terrorism of this type is not a part of New Zealand’s social and cultural tapestry. It is not in the Government’s interest, economical­ly, politicall­y or otherwise, to limit freedom of informatio­n to its Kiwi citizens, particular­ly in today’s era of ubiquitous digital communicat­ions.

I would suggest, therefore, that banning this manifesto is simultaneo­usly an act of tokenism and a measured response by the Government to appease an appalled nation that something tangible is being done.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from New Zealand