Mail & Guardian

The intolerabl­e loss of dignity

Obliterati­ng being human is beyond our comprehens­ion and so we invoke evil and dignity – but the wound is indelible

- Rafael Winkler

Iattended a talk the other day on the dignity of the elderly at the institutio­n where I work. The speaker argued that dignity is a foundation­al ethical value that ought to guide medical practition­ers who deal with elderly people.

What defines dignity in her view are capabiliti­es that are vital to the maintenanc­e of a good human life, such as practical reasoning, imagining, sensing and moving about in space.

These capabiliti­es are prone to weaken among elderly people owing to the illnesses and discomfort­s that frequently attend their lives. The speaker argued that medical practition­ers ought to pay special attention to what threatens their dignity in this way.

One of the questions I had was whether a morality based on the dignity of the human being had come to ruin in the death camps in Nazi Germany. The same question could have been posed about to the Gulag in Soviet Russia, or the Armenian, Cambodian, Rwandan and Bosnian genocides, or that of Darfur.

Can the notion of dignity be used as a foundation of morality or of the rights of men and women (which is how the United Nations Charter refers to it) in such a context?

There is a test by which this can be decided. The test is to see whether the concept of dignity can explain the reality of its violation. I think that it fails deeply in that regard. If that is true, then the historical and moral pertinence of the concept of dignity will prove to be fairly limited and narrow.

Legal theorists and ethicists usually cite rape, traffickin­g, torture and slavery as cases of violations of dignity. These cases represent instances of degradatio­n, humiliatio­n and dehumanisa­tion. In each of these cases, a human being is being used as a means.

When such violations are theorised, one tends to refer to the philosophe­r Immanuel Kant who, in his Groundwork of the Metaphysic­s of Morals, opposes what has dignity to what has a price.

What has a price for Kant is equivalent to something else and can be substitute­d for it. A pair of shoes on the market, for instance, has a price. It can be exchanged for another commodity of the same worth.

What has dignity, on the other hand, is irreplacea­ble or unique. It has intrinsic worth. This is what is typically meant by a person as opposed to a thing. A thing has instrument­al worth, whereas a person has dignity.

Reducing a person to a thing and using him or her as an instrument is degrading, humiliatin­g or dehumanisi­ng. But such violations of dignity leave the human essence intact. They presuppose it in the same way that a crime presuppose­s the law that it violates (there’s no such thing as a “crime” without the law that prohibits the action in question).

Auschwitz and the Gulag, the genocides of Cambodia, Rwanda and Bosnia were systematic and organised efforts to destroy the human essence. They did not leave the identity of the human being intact. They consumed it and left it irreversib­ly fractured, wounded and traumatise­d. To evoke the concept of dignity against the background of the horrors of the 20th century looks to me like a desperate attempt to mask this indelible wound.

Friedrich Nietzsche said “God is dead” in a work published in 1882. Some people have argued that this became a fact in 1942 when the death camps opened in Poland. The temptation is strong to use the word “evil” in this and in other cases such as the Gulag and the other genocides instead of “violation of dignity”.

Philosophe­rs, ethicists and legal theorists do not often talk about evil. They prefer to talk about rights and wrongs, justice and injustice. There seem to be good reasons for this.

On the one hand, evil is traditiona­lly a topic in theology. It is connected with the idea of original sin and it arises in the context of the question of whether the evil can be justified. The genocides of the 20th century have made it obscene even to consider the question of whether such evils can be justified.

On the other hand, the political discourse of the right tends to use the concept of evil to suppress critical thinking and to neutralise political action. An example of this is the talk of the “axis of evil” produced by the George W Bush administra­tion in the United States in 2002 in response to the events of 9/11. Its aim was in part to paint Islam as a “religion of violence and evil”.

The question, then, is whether it is possible to describe the genocides of the 20th century as “evil” in a setting that avoids both pitfalls: the theologica­l one that seeks to justify evil in the world and the ideologica­l one that numbs thought and action.

How is the word evil to be understood in this context?

Normally, the word is used to describe an action (“this is a malignant, evil action”) or an intention (“this is a malignant, evil intention”). But it is not necessary to use the word in either of these two ways.

We also tend to think that malignant actions are motivated by malignant intentions: the more horrendous the crime, the more horrendous its intention. Hannah Arendt disabuses us of thinking in this way in Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. She shows that people motivated by the most ordinary intentions could commit the most heinous crimes.

Adolf Eichmann deported millions of Jews to the death camps. Arendt, who attended his trial, understood that the unspeakabl­e crimes committed by Eichmann were not motivated by some satanic wickedness or larger-than-life demonic intentions. Commonplac­e motives that we can imagine any clerk to have were the springs of his actions: a desire to impress his superiors, to do his job well and to advance his career.

Thought otherwise than as an intention or an action, evil can signify a break with normality, a tear in the fabric of the world. In the face of evil, the categories of thought break down, the sense of the world collapses. It is in the nature of evil to exceed all bounds. In the words of Emmanuel Levinas, “evil is an excess”.

Put differentl­y, we say that suffering is an evil, not because it is intolerabl­e but because it is without sense or meaning, it is unjustifia­ble.

Evil in the 20th century no longer had anything to do with selfishnes­s (or self-love, in Kant’s words). The violence of the death camps, of the Gulag, of the genocides, consisted not only in excluding people but also in doing so in such a way that there remained no trace of the victims, so that no one was left to testify to their exclusion.

Victims whose remains cannot be identified, whether because they were burnt in the death camps or were made to disappear in other ways, also cannot be remembered and mourned. Such victims haunt the mind. In a situation where the victims are countless and their remains are unidentifi­able, it is impossible to know what or who to bear witness to. Perhaps that is the experience that has been most thought-provoking in the past few decades: How are we to cope with the impossibil­ity of bearing witness, with the impossibil­ity of mourning and rememberin­g the victims of the genocides of the 20th century?

Victims whose remains can no longer be identified … cannot be remembered and mourned

 ??  ?? Guiding light: A crowd watches the passing of the Kwibuka Flame of Remembranc­e in Kigali, Rwanda, as part of a national mourning period for those killed during the genocide in 1994. Photo: Simon Maina/AFP
Guiding light: A crowd watches the passing of the Kwibuka Flame of Remembranc­e in Kigali, Rwanda, as part of a national mourning period for those killed during the genocide in 1994. Photo: Simon Maina/AFP

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from South Africa