Bangkok Post

Hold Brexit con artists to account

- BERNARD-HENRI LÉVY ©2019 PROJECT SYNDICATE

In late May, the Westminste­r Magistrate­s’ Court decided to hear a complaint brought by activist Marcus Ball, who had accused Boris Johnson, the former UK foreign secretary who is now leading the field to succeed Theresa May as prime minister, of lying during the 2016 Brexit referendum campaign. London’s High Court, however, reversed that decision and quashed the summons that would have compelled Mr Johnson to testify about the Brexit campaign in open court.

The High Court’s decision is regrettabl­e. A public hearing would have been highly welcome for two reasons. It would have exposed the lies of the Brexiteers — which have always seemed to me to be the best argument of those who want to stop Brexit. And, more generally, a hearing would have highlighte­d the danger that such lies can pose to a democracy.

Of course, the United Kingdom should be free to choose to become Little England again. After all, population­s have as much right to commit suicide as individual­s do. But this is on one condition: that the choice is informed, deliberate, and freely made.

No one should be pushed into it by harassment or incitement — an offence which, in the case of actual suicide, is subject to severe punishment.

Yet something akin to that happened during the campaign leading up to the Brexit vote. The British people, far from acting in full awareness of the issues, were misled. The examples of misinforma­tion and barely disguised lies that clouded voters’ judgement are too numerous to count.

Allowing Mr Ball’s complaint to proceed would have shown this. A court hearing would have demonstrat­ed that the debate prior to the referendum was not honest. It would have establishe­d that the vote in favour of Brexit and the popular acceptance of its consequenc­es were not matters of informed consent.

And that would have provided the best possible argument that UK citizens should have the opportunit­y to reconsider their decision. In addition, the court proceeding­s would have had the further, even more essential, virtue of underlinin­g how the toleration of lies can gravely harm a democracy.

Mr Johnson’s supporters argued that it would not have been right to permit a single judge to decide a debate of Brexit’s magnitude, and that the courts are not appellate chambers for the settlement of democratic disputes. Fair enough — but then there are different types of dispute.

For example, it is one thing to bet that England, set free from Old Europe, would return to the high seas and prosper. But it is quite another to promote that bet by deploying flagrant untruths — for example, that Europe was costing the £350 million (1.4 billion baht) per week — which, once the bettors had wagered their life savings, were sneeringly acknowledg­ed to have been untrue.

In a similar vein, it is one thing to believe, as US neoconserv­atives did, that democracy could be implemente­d in Iraq at the barrel of a gun, and to argue in good faith on the basis of that belief. But it is quite another to try to settle the issue at the United Nations by displaying bogus vials of powder that supposedly establishe­d the presence of non-existent weapons of mass destructio­n.

Both the Iraq War and Brexit illustrate a simple but essential distinctio­n for any democracy. On the one hand, there is a fair fight between opposing points of view conducted in an arena governed by clear rules, which is what the public space should be. On the other hand, there is a struggle to the death in which no holds are barred and no punch can land too low, including the punch that is like no other: the lie.

Lying is different because it erodes our faith in public discourse. It poisons the climate in which political speech is conceived, mines the fields on which opposing views must contend, and removes even the possibilit­y of the fair reckonings that are the hallmark of democracy.

The contrast is between Nietzsche’s “perspectiv­ism”, in which competing “evaluation­s” joust endlessly with one another, and the “lie” of Machiavell­i, which allows the deceptive prince to have the last word when closing a debate.

Or, more precisely, the contrast pits Machiavell­i against himself. In The Prince, Machiavell­i does not so much legitimise the right to lie as alert people to the way in which the tyrant, by bestowing this right upon himself, renders further debate impossible. However, in the Discourses, Machiavell­i defends the right to deploy all means — except the right to lie — to ensure that one’s passion and point of view prevail.

We know well the damage that corrupt leaders do to their people. We should therefore have much more to say about the quintessen­tial corruption entailed by tolerating lies.

Such tolerance allows the poison to spread through the body and soul of democracy, underminin­g democracy’s institutio­ns by attacking the invisible norms and tacit understand­ings that support them. And that is what any trial of the Brexiteer charlatans would demonstrat­e.

Bernard-Henri Lévy is one of the founders of the ‘Nouveaux Philosophe­s’ (New Philosophe­rs) movement. He is the author, most recently, of ‘The Empire and the Five Kings’.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Thailand