All About Space

Putting consciousn­ess back into the cosmos

-

Dr Philip Goff, a philosophe­r and consciousn­ess researcher at Durham University, thinks everything in the physical world has a degree of consciousn­ess. He’s the author of Galileo’s Error: Foundation­s for a New Science of Consciousn­ess

Panpsychis­m says that all things have a mind-like quality, thereby pointing to the possibilit­y of the universe being conscious, but how does it explain this? The current resurgence of interest in panpsychis­m is rooted in important work from the 1920s by the philosophe­r and Nobel laureate Bertrand Russell and the scientist Arthur Eddington, who was, incidental­ly, the first scientist to experiment­ally confirm Einstein’s general theory of relativity.

The starting point for Russell and Eddington is that physical science tells us what matter does, but it doesn't tell us what it actually is. Physics tells us, for example, that particles have mass and charge, and these properties are completely defined in terms of behaviour: things like attraction, repulsion and resistance to accelerati­on. This is all about what stuff does. Doing physics is like playing chess without knowing what the pieces are made of.

The genius of Russell and Eddington was to see the connection to the problem of consciousn­ess. If physics leaves completely open what an electron is, then physics is left open to the theoretica­l possibilit­y that an electron is a form of consciousn­ess. Russell and Eddington saw the potential for bringing together what Galileo

Galilei had separated: the quantitati­ve story of physics and the qualitativ­e story of consciousn­ess. According to panpsychis­m, the former is the story of what matter does, while the latter is the story of what matter is. Matter and consciousn­ess are inseparabl­e: two sides of the same coin.

When people say ’the universe might be conscious’, what do they mean?

It is important not to anthropoce­ntrically focus on human consciousn­ess: nobody is claiming that an electron has the consciousn­ess of a human being. What it’s like to be a human being is a rich and complex affair involving detailed visual and auditory experience­s, deep emotions, and subtle thoughts. What it’s like to be a sheep is significan­tly simpler. What it’s like to be a mouse is simpler still. As we move to simpler and simpler forms of life, we find simpler and simpler forms of conscious experience. It’s possible that this continues right down to the basic building blocks of matter, with electrons and quarks having incredibly simple forms of conscious experience to reflect their incredibly simple nature.

If the universe has experience, on the other hand, it will be incredibly complex, correspond­ing to the complex physical structure of space and time. However, that doesn’t mean the universe is a kind of self-aware, intelligen­t agent. You need millions of years of evolution to get these traits. Rather, the experience of the universe is probably just a meaningles­s mess.

Integrated informatio­n theory is compatible with panpsychis­m. How can it explain consciousn­ess? We can divide the science of consciousn­ess into an experiment­al bit and a scientific bit. The aim of the experiment­al bit is to track the neural correlates of consciousn­ess (NCC) to work out which kinds of brain activity correspond to which kinds of experience. The aim of the theoretica­l bit is to explain these correlatio­ns. Why is it that certain kinds of physical activity give rise to certain forms of experience? IIT is one answer to the experiment­al question: according to IIT, consciousn­ess is correlated with maximal integrated informatio­n. But it lacks a plausible answer to this theoretica­l question: why is maximal integrated informatio­n correlated with experience?

 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United Kingdom