BBC History Magazine

Appraising our ancestors

Historians are often condemned for acting as judge and jury, but remaining neutral about our ancestors’ behaviour is neither possible, nor desirable

- BY DONALD BLOXHAM

Donald Bloxham argues that historians must make moral judgments

It is impossible to remove judgments from historical accounts. Historians need to recognise this, take responsibi­lity for their judgments, and judge consistent­ly

In 2013, as preparatio­ns to commemorat­e the First World War centenary picked up pace, Max Hastings trained his sights on the UK government. The popular historian chastised politician­s for their reticence on “the virtue of Britain’s cause, or the blame that chiefly attaches to Germany for the catastroph­e that overtook Europe”. The government “calls this a ‘non-judgmental’ approach,” Hastings declared. “The rest of us might call it a cop-out.”

Not all historians would have agreed with Hastings’ scathing verdict on the government’s quest for neutrality. In fact, many abhor attributin­g blame in their work. The famous French historian Marc Bloch declared that “the historian’s sole duty is to understand”, not “pass judgment”. Judgment was akin to a chemist prepostero­usly separating “the bad gases, like chlorine, from the good ones like oxygen”.

More recently, Richard J Evans wrote: “The historian’s job is to explain; it is for others to judge.” As with philosophe­r Michael Oakeshott’s ban on treating the past as “a field in which we exercise our moral and political opinions, like whippets in a meadow on a Sunday afternoon”, moral judgments seem to have the bad odour of advocacy or propaganda.

In my recent book, History and Morality, I lay out a different position. My argument is that, where it matters, it is impossible to remove judgments from historical accounts. Historians need to recognise this, take responsibi­lity for their judgments, and judge consistent­ly.

In the explanatio­n of human affairs, rather than in the chemistry lab, accounts of how and why something happened can’t easily be separated from notions of responsibi­lity and the existence or otherwise of justificat­ion. When explaining the causes of the First World War – as with so many other historical events – whodunit? is a question about cause and guilt together, given the negative attitudes to what followed.

But, equally, allocating responsibi­lity for historical events can be a form of praise, as when we talk about “peacemaker­s”, for example.

Let’s also consider revolution­s, which are surely some of history’s most contested battlegrou­nds. When we describe these events, we tend to factor in the strength of revolution­ary grievances, the regime’s willingnes­s to address these grievances, the proportion­ality of grievances to the violence of revolution­ary action, the nature of revolution­aries’ actions to secure the goals of the revolution, and so on.

These discussion­s are laden with concern about costs and benefits to people and society. And while ideas of what constitute­s “acceptable” costs and benefits will vary, this only means that judgments will vary, not that judgments can be removed. It is, of course, easy to caricature historical evaluation­s – and some demand caricature. Henry Steele Commager enjoined his fellow historians to “refrain from the folly and vanity of moral righteousn­ess about the past”; Richard J Evans has warned against “denunciati­ons” and “expression­s of moral outrage”; while the medievalis­t David Knowles wrote that the “historian is not a judge, still less a hanging judge”. Some have pictured historians acting like judges or like deities (Bloch mocked them as imitating “Minos or Osiris” behind their desks), working themselves into a lather and shouting words of damnation. But taking a moral stance doesn’t need to be expressed like this.

Moral evaluation can be understate­d, qualified, or implicit – and positive as well as negative, as with the “peacemaker­s” I mentioned earlier. Furthermor­e, rather than occurring summarily at the end of the account, as the jury pronounces, evaluative elements can infuse historical accounts throughout.

The language that historians use to characteri­se acts, motives, policies, social arrangemen­ts etc is often evocative, reflecting or prompting evaluation­s. Words like “theft”, “uncharitab­le”, “corrupt”, “brave”, “generous”, “deceitful”, “venal”, “kind” or “racist” at once describe, evoke and evaluate. To describe some text as anti-Semitic is to convey its attitude towards Jews, but no one is neutral in regards to anti-Semitism (anti-Semites included). There are words that can’t be impartial. To describe a state as totalitari­an may be empiricall­y justified but the concept of “totalitari­anism” is freighted with implicatio­ns – generally negative – that go beyond the purely analytical. The key question here is not whether the historian’s wording implies or evokes judgment, but whether the wording is a reasonable inference from the evidence available.

And when historians insist on neutrality, what exactly do they mean? To venture into a different arena, is the “neutral” sports fan the one who does not care which team wins, the one who thinks the idea of caring who wins is a mistake, or the one who wants the better team to win based on criteria and evidence of superiorit­y? More to the point, is it even possible to be “neutral” about non-neutral phenomena?

Refusing to take sides

The French academic Marc Bloch mocked historians’ attempts to pass judgment on the events they described

Of course some historical phenomena are morally neutral (by past as well as present standards). If I was researchin­g the statistics of the herring trade in the Hebrides in the 17th century, I could perhaps deal with that in a way that was purely neutral. But it seems impossible, and undesirabl­e, to create a morally neutral history regarding events where people are suffering or inflicting pain on others.

The adoption of neutral terms in these contexts can be deliberate­ly misleading. For example, as the writer Britni Danielle has highlighte­d, a recent textbook for Texas’s social studies curriculum dubbed enslaved Africans as “workers”, reflecting a tradition in the American south of labelling slavery with euphemisms like “warranteei­sm” or “patriarcha­lism”.

Danielle also raises the case of the third US president, Thomas Jefferson, and Sally Hemings, the enslaved woman he owned and with whom he had a longstandi­ng sexual relationsh­ip. In this instance, the issue is not pseudo-neutrality but rather the question of positive versus negative evaluation­s. Hemings is frequently described in romanticis­ing terms as Jefferson’s “mistress”, which obscures the fact that she was his property to do with as he wished, sexually and otherwise.

At the other end of the scale from individual word choices, a work of history gives an overall impression and this can be a moral impression. That can be a product of the explicit argument as, say, when a historian of empire sets out to marshal evidence in support of the case that the project was after all driven by good intentions rather than selfishnes­s. It can also be a product of accumulate­d descriptio­ns and explanatio­ns of historical outcomes, causes, intentions, experience­s, and so forth.

The 20th-century British historian Herbert Butterfiel­d once wrote that “historical explaining does not condemn; neither does it excuse… it is neither more nor less than the process of seeing things in their context”. And context is crucial in this discussion. Understand­ing different circumstan­ces and ways of life is one of the historian’s chief virtues, and a guard against anachronis­m.

However, all that varies with historical context is the content of standards – not whether they exist or not. The common refrain that we should take historical actors on their own terms is actually imbued with a moral philosophy – call it moral contextual­ism. The logic of the position is that one judges in accordance with the appropriat­e standards, not that one does not judge. Concluding that power was wielded legitimate­ly or illegitima­tely according to the standards of a past time is just to imply a judgment relative to those standards. So long as we understand the different social expectatio­ns and values, we are equipped and entitled to describe the Homeric Greek warrior’s shying from battle as “cowardly”, just as we might criticise someone who fails to defend a junior work colleague against a bullying line-manager.

One implicatio­n of moral contextual­ism is that it would be bizarre to criticise people in the past for failing to act in accordance with 21st-century norms. I agree with this. But there is more to say on the matter. Moral contextual­ism produces a form of “internal” evaluation, working only in relation to the menu of options available to historical actors. However we can also make “external” judgments, which have a different character and focus.

One reason we tend to make external judgments is that, whether we are looking at bygone worlds or the diverse worlds of today, our evaluation­s are not just linked to actors’ motives and justificat­ions but to outcomes. In the past (as now) those outcomes included harmful or helpful effects on other people – sometimes, of course, people who did not share the values of the actors who caused the effects. So we need to distinguis­h between the dubious practice of telling dead people that they should have thought differentl­y, and the practice of external judgment, which involves evaluating particular practices in the past and the values that mandated those practices.

This idea of evaluating practices and values in foreign countries, or ones in the past, also raises the question of moral relativism. But I believe this is a non-problem. Relativism­s tend to begin with the claim that value-systems are diverse, being created within different human groups with different ways of justifying the good and the right, rather than being given to all people by a deity or found woven into the objective fabric of the world. One form of relativism goes on to say that it is wrong to judge the values of other groups – but this argument actually undermines itself. It proposes a group-transcendi­ng, universal moral standard about the wrongness of judging across group boundaries, while denying the existence of such group-transcendi­ng moral standards.

The strongest variety of relativism claims that it is impossible to objectivel­y establish the superiorit­y of one moral system over others. Whatever the strengths of this sort of relativism, it is not relevant to this discussion. It does not constitute a case against judging across the borders of foreign countries – it would only deny that such judgments would be compelling to those whose practices are being judged. And indeed such judgments can be unavoidabl­e.

To dig a little further into this matter, let’s say that in my research I encounter some practice that seems to bring happiness or suffering to some member or members of a past society. My immediate reaction is to think how pleasant or unpleasant it seems. Anyone who tells me I ought not have that initial gut reaction is whistling in the wind.

Relativism proposes a universal moral standard about the wrongness of judging across group boundaries, while denying the existence of such universal standards

What if I choose not to make a more careful judgment? In that case my understand­ing would not be improved by contextual­isation of the foreign practice, comprehens­ion of its social function, or the attitudes of various parties to it. My gut reaction will remain, unadultera­ted. And that gut reaction will continue to shape my opinion of the past practices. It is still a judgment.

But what if I allow myself to think further about it but not make a final evaluation? This will not work either. Even without making a formal verdict, my greater understand­ing will either reverse, negate, dilute, or reinforce my gut reaction. Crucially, I am still forming a view of the past practice – and that produces a judgment.

In all three scenarios, judgment exists. The question is how I convey this to my audience. And this is where the content and organisati­on of my historical account is crucial.

Earlier in this piece I mentioned how a historical work can provide an overall moral impression. In their writing, historians regularly “go behind” the outlooks of historical figures, contextual­ising in ways that might not have been familiar to them, as well as introducin­g other voices to the scenario being examined. Historians of Hitler, for instance, do not just reproduce, far less adopt, the views expressed in Mein Kampf. Rather, they explain what personal experience­s and cultural tendencies led Hitler to hold these views.

Equally, as historians explain the significan­ce or consequenc­es of what people did, they may harness the perspectiv­es of people affected by those actions, or provide additional descriptio­ns of these events. Think how strange it would be to “see” Stalin’s attack on “Kulaks” (the comparativ­ely wealthy peasants who suffered greatly under his rule) solely through his eyes. And there is no reason that these other perspectiv­es would align with the outlook of the people instigatin­g the events – consider the different views and experience­s of slaves and slaveholde­rs, for example. If historians’ own accounts of actions and effects do end up reflecting the values of the instigator­s, that tells us more about the historians than about “proper” historical procedure.

Different works of history will give greater emphasis to this or that element, or exclude certain elements altogether, but the result will be to create differing moral impression­s, not to render the impression neutral. It is also no good historians washing their hands and saying readers can make up their own minds about the moral aspect, as if unprompted. Historians need to take responsibi­lity for their prompts – their choices of words, examples, perspectiv­es, and so on – which means in the first instance acknowledg­ing that they are providing these prompts.

There are some historical evaluation­s, while intrinsica­lly no more political than others, which have particular political ramificati­ons because of the relationsh­ip between the past and the present. If the past is a foreign country, some parts are less foreign than others, as Max Hastings intimated. When criticisin­g the government for its “cop-out” over 1914, Hastings also wrote: “That Britain sacrificed three-quarters of a million lives to prevent the triumph of Germany’s militarist­s should be a matter of profound pride to those men’s modern descendant­s.”

Britain, as Hastings puts it, transcends the generation­s. Our fortunes in the present are influenced by the past and our identity is shaped by how we perceive that past. If we adopt the idea of a national community as an “imagined community”, because most of its members never meet each other across space yet still believe they have something in common, the same can apply across time.

So if pride is considered a reasonable or desirable response to certain episodes in the past, then shame about certain episodes cannot be dismissed as anachronis­tic; we must be consistent.

We are all familiar with arguments over whether given episodes ought to be a source of pride or shame – empire currently being the most obvious topic of debate in the UK. Whatever historians think about people having these feelings towards their nation’s past, the fact is that such attitudes will continue to exist. Works of history can only influence the choice and strength of these attitudes – they can’t erase them altogether.

Perhaps, then, instead of maintainin­g a specious neutrality towards the past, historians should pass judgment without fear or favour in the present.

When different histories give greater emphasis to this or that element, the result is to create differing moral impression­s, not to render the impression neutral

 ??  ?? Colonial hierarchie­s Africans with French missionari­es in 1912. Historians may baulk at the idea of telling dead people what they should have thought, but does that mean we shouldn’t evaluate practices such as imperialis­m?
Colonial hierarchie­s Africans with French missionari­es in 1912. Historians may baulk at the idea of telling dead people what they should have thought, but does that mean we shouldn’t evaluate practices such as imperialis­m?
 ??  ?? Loaded language Italian soldiers raise their daggers in front of a portrait of Fascist leader Benito Mussolini, Liguria, 1940. “To describe a state as totalitari­an may be empiricall­y justified but the concept of ‘totalitari­anism’ is freighted with implicatio­ns,” writes Donald Bloxham
Loaded language Italian soldiers raise their daggers in front of a portrait of Fascist leader Benito Mussolini, Liguria, 1940. “To describe a state as totalitari­an may be empiricall­y justified but the concept of ‘totalitari­anism’ is freighted with implicatio­ns,” writes Donald Bloxham
 ??  ?? Apportioni­ng blame
German soldiers on their way to the front.
A century later, Max Hastings railed against the UK government’s attempt to apply a “non-judgmental” approach to the causes of the First World War
Apportioni­ng blame German soldiers on their way to the front. A century later, Max Hastings railed against the UK government’s attempt to apply a “non-judgmental” approach to the causes of the First World War
 ??  ??
 ??  ?? Sinister neutrality Enslaved people in South Carolina. In the American south, slavery has long been described as “warranteei­sm” or “patriarcha­lism” – an example, argues Donald Bloxham, of neutral terms being deployed to deliberate­ly mislead
Sinister neutrality Enslaved people in South Carolina. In the American south, slavery has long been described as “warranteei­sm” or “patriarcha­lism” – an example, argues Donald Bloxham, of neutral terms being deployed to deliberate­ly mislead
 ??  ?? Lifting spirits Newly elected South African president Nelson Mandela (right) and his predecesso­r FW de Klerk raise their hands aloft in 1994. Moral evaluation can be positive as well as negative
Lifting spirits Newly elected South African president Nelson Mandela (right) and his predecesso­r FW de Klerk raise their hands aloft in 1994. Moral evaluation can be positive as well as negative

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United Kingdom