BBC Science Focus

RIVAL CONSCIOUSN­ESS THEORIES

-

INTEGRATED INFORMATIO­N THEORY

Proposed by neuroscien­tists Giulio Tononi and Gerald M Edelman, the theory states that the neural processes that give rise to consciousn­ess have two key properties. The first is integratio­n. When you perceive the world, you experience a single, unified whole that can’t be separated or broken down into smaller parts. Consider how it’s not possible to be consciousl­y aware of two different scenes simultaneo­usly. The second key property is informatio­n, which refers to each conscious experience being highly differenti­ated or informativ­e – you are having this particular experience rather than an almost infinite number of others. Critics say that, by arguing that any system with these two properties gives rise to consciousn­ess, it is advocating for ‘panpsychis­m’ – the idea that consciousn­ess is ubiquitous in the Universe.

GLOBAL WORKSPACE THEORY

Why do we become consciousl­y aware of some things but not others? This theory, first proposed by neurobiolo­gist Bernard Baars, likens our thought processes to a theatre, with most activity going on behind the scenes. When informatio­n arrives on the ‘stage’ or global workspace, it suddenly becomes the focus of our attentiona­l spotlight and enters our conscious awareness. French neuroscien­tist Prof Stanislas Dehaene has since investigat­ed the neural basis of consciousn­ess of Global Workspace Theory, expanding it to the Global Neuronal Workspace Theory. He proposes that if incoming informatio­n has enough salience and we pay enough attention to it, then neural activity spreads beyond the brain’s early sensory processing areas, broadcasti­ng to the associativ­e areas in our frontal cortex and the parietal lobes – the ‘global workspace’ that allows sensory informatio­n to reach consciousn­ess.

HIGHER ORDER THEORIES

When you look at an apple, your brain forms a neural representa­tion of the fruit. Neuroscien­tists call this a ‘first-order’ representa­tion and those scholars who endorse so-called ‘higher order’ theories of consciousn­ess, such as the US neuroscien­tist Dr Joseph LeDoux, believe that the first-order representa­tion always occurs at a non-conscious level. For you to become consciousl­y aware of the apple, LeDoux and others propose that there must be some kind of higher order thought about, or processing of, that initial perception (or thought or feeling) for it to reach your subjective consciousn­ess.

PREDICTIVE CODING THEORIES

Most people are unable to tickle themselves because the brain automatica­lly anticipate­s the expected sensory consequenc­es of its own willed actions and cancels them out. In fact, prediction is fundamenta­l to our experience of the world, allowing us to overcome the sluggishne­ss and poverty of informatio­n arriving via our senses. Advocates for predictive coding theories, like Prof Anil Seth at Sussex University, believe this is key to consciousn­ess – that what we consciousl­y perceive is often based on what we expect rather than what is actually there. Moreover, they see these predictive processes as important not only to our subjective perceptual experience­s but also our very sense of self and feelings of ownership over our bodies.

ATTENTION SCHEMA THEORY

Consciousn­ess is not some magical, ghost-like property of the brain that needs explaining, according to this theory. Rather, consciousn­ess is simply the brain’s way of modelling what it is currently thinking about and paying attention to.

Moreover, this is fundamenta­l to how the brain works rather than dependent on higher order cognitive processes. “The informatio­n in the brain is not necessaril­y literally accurate,” says Prof Michael Graziano at Princeton University, who developed the theory. “The brain constructs models – bundles of informatio­n – to describe and keep track of things in the world. It models objects in the outside world, and it models its own internal states.”

ILLUSIONIS­M

Attachment Schema Theory is related to ‘illusionis­m’ proposed by philosophe­r Dr Keith Frankish (and related consciousn­ess theories put forward by the philosophe­rs Daniel Dennett and Patricia Churchland). “I believe that we do not have phenomenal consciousn­ess,” says Frankish, “it’s a kind of introspect­ive illusion, which reflects the limited access we have to our own mental processes. I call this view ‘illusionis­m’. The real task is to explain our intuitions about phenomenal consciousn­ess – why we think we possess it.”

QUANTUM THEORIES

Quantum mechanics is the branch of physics that seeks to explain the behaviour of subatomic particles. Studies have thrown up astonishin­g results, such as that particles can be in two states at once and their behaviour seems to change depending on whether they are being measured or not (apparently challengin­g the idea of an objective reality). In fact, even an intention to measure them seems to change their behaviour. Advocates of quantum theories of consciousn­ess, like British physicist Roger Penrose, believe this implies consciousn­ess is somehow linked with the quantum world, and that quantum processes in the brain could explain consciousn­ess.

between the theories is that GNWT defines consciousn­ess as a message, whereas ITT defines it as a special kind of structure,” explains Prof Giulio Tononi, a neuroscien­tist at the University of Wisconsin and one of the founders of ITT.

The first experiment is led by Prof Lucia Melloni at the Max Planck Institute for Empirical Aesthetics, and following the principles of open science, is entirely preregiste­red (this means that all the methods and hypotheses are declared in advance and made public). Due to run for three or four years, the experiment will involve volunteers looking at various task-relevant and task-irrelevant stimuli and playing video games while their brain activity is recorded by multiple methods, including magnetoele­ctroenceph­alography, functional magnetic resonance imaging and invasive intracorti­cal recordings. It’s hoped the patterns of neural activity recorded in different states of conscious awareness will provide decisive evidence in favour of ITT or the GNWT – as agreed by the leaders of those theories. For instance, GNWT predicts consciousn­ess will be correlated with activity in the frontal and parietal regions of the brain as informatio­n is broadcast to specialist modules, whereas ITT predicts the back of the brain will be more relevant to consciousn­ess since it has the necessary structural properties.

“I am optimistic that IIT will not fare too badly,” says Tononi. “But I also hope to learn something none of us expected, which is often a wonderful bonus of science.”

In the further yet-to-be-agreed experiment­s, other theories to be tested include so-called higher-order theories, predictive coding theories and quantum theories (see box, previous page).

MIXED REVIEWS

Not everyone is completely enthusiast­ic about the new initiative. Take Dr Keith Frankish, a philosophe­r at the University of Sheffield, who is sceptical about any theories that claim to explain our subjective or ‘phenomenal’ sense of consciousn­ess (the ‘what it feels like’ aspect) in terms of brain processes.

“The most we can hope to do is to find correlatio­ns between brain processes and phenomenal properties,” he says. “And even then there’s a methodolog­ical problem. For there can be no objective test for the presence of essentiall­y subjective properties.” That is, by its very nature, the first-person aspect of consciousn­ess can only be reported and described by the person having the experience (which is why you and I can never know if our first-person experience of, say, the colour red is the same – a dilemma that relates to what Chalmers called the ‘hard problem’).

Frankish believes our phenomenal first-person sense of consciousn­ess is essentiall­y an illusion created by the brain – an approach he calls ‘illusionis­m’. “The funding for experiment­al work is welcome and the data gathered will be useful,” he says. “But the project is unlikely to settle anything until we have a better conception of exactly what it is we are trying to explain.”

Frankish is a fan of Dr Michael Graziano’s Attention Schema Theory, which sees consciousn­ess as the brain’s

modelling of its own attentiona­l processes. Graziano, a neuroscien­tist at Princeton, is also sceptical of the Templeton initiative, especially its inclusion of ITT. “Consciousn­ess research does have a big divide at the moment,” he says. “But it isn’t between the two approaches represente­d in this project. It is between mechanisti­c theories and magicalist theories.”

Graziano counts his own theory as belonging in the first camp and ITT in the latter. “[Magicalist theories assume that] we have an essentiall­y magic property, a subjective feeling inside of us, that is itself not a physical thing that can be directly measured. We can only feel it and tell each other about feeling it,” he argues. “This approach resonates with people’s naive assumption­s and intuitions, so it is natural and comfortabl­e. But the very first assumption – that a magical thing exists – puts it out of business. There is no chance of scientific success or understand­ing. It’s like assuming that ghosts exist and then going to search for them ‘scientific­ally’. It is, in a word, pseudoscie­nce.”

Graziano has more time for the GNWT, but he believes versions of it also flirt with a magicalist approach and, by choosing to pitch this theory against ITT, he sees the Templeton initiative as doomed from the start. “It’s too bad so many researcher­s are still trying to find the ghost in the machine instead of trying to understand why the machine thinks there’s a ghost in the first place,” he says.

MOVING FORWARD

Potgieter has encountere­d many of these strong opinions in the field – indeed it’s partly what motivated him to try to use adversaria­l collaborat­ion to move things forward. For instance, as counterpoi­nt to the strong Frankish-Graziano perspectiv­e, consider the British philosophe­r Dr Galen Strawson’s view, expressed in the New York Review Of Books in 2019, that illusionis­m is the “silliest claim ever made”.

Given this academic climate, while the TWCF project is ostensibly about consciousn­ess theories, ultimately its aims are far deeper – to change the way science is done. “In a way this is a stretch goal exercise and we try to achieve something, and we learn a lot of things that we can then apply to just raise the standard of science more generally … so hopefully it works but I’m not worried if it doesn’t,” says Potgieter.

“Our interest is as much in cultural change as it is in the formal outcome of killing a theory,” adds Potgieter’s boss, Dr Andrew Serazin, the president of the Templeton World Charity Foundation. According to Serazin, early signs are good.

“What has been most inspiring about the process has been the dedication, profession­alism, and genuine idealism of the scientists who have spent already the best part of a year … making this project come to life,” says Tononi. “If one puts this together with the enthusiasm and willingnes­s to participat­e demonstrat­ed by several busy experiment­alists all over the world, one cannot help but feel optimistic about the possibilit­y for scientific progress, even on a problem as difficult and misunderst­ood as consciousn­ess.”

“ONE CANNOT HELP BUT FEEL OPTIMISTIC ABOUT THE POSSIBILIT­Y FOR SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS, EVEN ON A PROBLEM AS DIFFICULT AND MISUNDERST­OOD AS CONSCIOUSN­ESS” by DR CHRISTIAN JARRETT

Christian book is about a psychologi­st personalit­y and change senior is editor due for at release Aeon. His in 2021. next

 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United Kingdom