Horse & Hound

Genetic technology

Scientific advancemen­ts can help us beat some equine conditions, but what are the possible ethical issues?

-

THE developmen­t of new genetic technologi­es is simultaneo­usly one of the most scientific­ally extraordin­ary and most ethically challengin­g aspects of modern veterinary medicine.

Over recent years, we have developed the ability not only to test adult horses for geneticall­y heritable traits, but also to screen equine embryos prior to transfer into a mare. With the advent of genetic editing, we stand poised at the beginning of an era in which humans can manipulate the equine genome in ways that can affect both current and future generation­s of horses.

However, while this offers us wonderful opportunit­ies to improve equine health and welfare, it also opens up some fascinatin­g ethical questions.

The sequencing of the equine genome in 2010 facilitate­d understand­ing of how diseases are inherited.

As of last year, 237 equine traits or disorders with a genetic basis had been catalogued by the University of Sydney. This knowledge enables breeders to avoid breeding from animals carrying the genes for diseases, particular­ly where the method of inheritanc­e is “autosomal recessive” – meaning that horses will show symptoms of this type of disease if they have two copies of the defective gene (one inherited from each parent).

A horse that inherits only one copy of the defective gene will not show signs of the disease. If he is crossed with another horse also carrying one copy, there is a 1:4 chance that the foal will inherit two copies and show symptoms.

Genetic testing enables us to identify so-called “carrier” animals, to avoid crossing them. Examples of diseases that can be tested for in this way include warmblood fragile foal syndrome; naked foal syndrome in the AkhalTeke, first described by scientists in 2017; and foal immunodefi­ciency syndrome affecting Fell and Dales ponies.

Other genetic diseases are inherited by a mechanism known as “autosomal dominant”, where an animal that inherits just one copy of the defective gene (from either parent) will show signs.

Since the severity of these signs may vary, it is not always easy to physically identify a gene carrier. Genetic testing is, again,

useful to prevent these diseases, such as malignant hypertherm­ia disorder in quarter horses, paint horses and Appaloosas.

Many breed societies, including the World Arabian Horse Organisati­on and various warmblood studbooks, now encourage voluntary genetic testing of breeding animals.

The American Quarter Horse Associatio­n insists that stallions are tested for five heritable diseases and will no longer register foals with specified genetic abnormalit­ies.

MORAL QUESTIONS

SUCH uses of genetic technologi­es are ethically uncomplica­ted. The “harm” caused to the animal being tested involves taking either a blood test or a hair sample, and is clearly outweighed by the benefit of avoiding breeding foals with debilitati­ng, painful and sometimes fatal health problems.

The ethics become more complicate­d when we consider that equine embryos can now be flushed out of a mare’s uterus and biopsied to test the embryonic cells for genetic disease. The intention is the same as that behind testing adult animals – to avoid foals being born which will suffer from disease.

An embryo found to be carrying the disease gene is discarded. Some people consider the killing of embryos morally problemati­c. Others believe it is a lesser harm than allowing foals to be born which will suffer and may die from genetic disease, particular­ly since embryos are considered incapable of suffering.

We can also carry out genetic testing for susceptibi­lity to sport-related injury and disease, a controvers­ial practice in humans that is not yet well developed in the horse. We do know that there is genetic variation in the risk of fracture in thoroughbr­ed racehorses, and that there is a genetic basis of equine exertional rhabdomyol­osis (sometimes termed azoturia, or tying up).

If our overall aim is to improve equine welfare, then testing to avoid breeding from animals carrying these genes must be an ethically “good thing”. Yet should we test for other traits, which have no direct impact on the future horse’s wellbeing but will affect the foal’s usefulness to humans?

The obvious example is testing for the “speed gene” in thoroughbr­eds, which can be used to inform decisions about breeding and whether horses are better suited to speed or stamina events (see box, left). Genetic testing can also identify the sex of an embryo before transferri­ng it, in order to produce only foals of the “desired” sex.

REWRITING THE CODE

THE ethical debate becomes even more complex when one considers the possibilit­y of genetic editing – a process that involves using an enzyme known as an endonuclea­se (typically the Cas-9 endonuclea­se) to “cut” the equine genome.

Scientists can then replace an unwanted gene with one that is desirable, or turn a gene on or off. Where gene editing is used in embryos, rather than in existing animals (which has been carried out experiment­ally in dogs), the changes will probably be heritable and will thus affect all future generation­s.

By geneticall­y editing embryos, we could remove disease genes or those that predispose to injury for good. To some people, such fundamenta­l human interferen­ce with nature is never justifiabl­e. Others may believe that it is justifiabl­e, and indeed ought to be done on welfare grounds.

The same techniques can be used to alter the equine genome to enhance performanc­e. This has already been reported by a group in Argentina, who have geneticall­y edited polo pony embryos to influence muscle mass.

Is this ethically justifiabl­e? All of the arguments mentioned so far about indirect, positive effects on welfare apply, but there is an additional aspect. In the current state of science, gene-editing can involve “off-target effects”.

These are unpredicta­ble, harmful side effects, such as those that cause cancers. Currently, they are poorly understood. Use of genetic editing is therefore slightly scary, in the sense that we don’t know exactly what is going to happen – we might make adverse changes to the equine genome which are heritable and cause problems in many generation­s.

We must consider such risks if we are aiming to improve equine health and welfare.

If the reason for genetic editing is to remove a disease gene, we may decide that the potential harms of off-target effects are outweighed by the benefits to future generation­s of avoiding disease. But if we’re aiming simply to “enhance performanc­e”, these risks may not be justified purely for our own benefit as humans.

The conundrum is that our ability to avoid off-target effects will never improve unless genetic editing is allowed. Given its huge positive potential, we should continue to explore its possibilit­ies – provided that the equine community works together to gather data and regulate use, protecting animal welfare.

“Geneticall­y editing embryos could remove disease genes for good”

 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ?? Above: genetic abnormalit­ies can be detected by testing a hair sample
Above: genetic abnormalit­ies can be detected by testing a hair sample

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United Kingdom