The Independent

Faith, proof and revelation

Our series continues with perhaps the major figure in scholastic tradition, Saint Thomas Aquinas, who drew from Aristotle for his teachings on reason and revelation

-

Saint Thomas Aquinas (1225/6–1274) was an Italian Catholic philosophe­r and a major figure – if not the major figure – in the scholastic tradition. He gave rise to the Thomistic school of philosophy, for a long while the primary philosophi­cal mainstay of the Roman Catholic Church.

The life of Thomas Aquinas ended in a manner not quite befitting a saint and a Dominican friar (the Dominican brotherhoo­d places value on a life of poverty and undertakes the begging of alms). He was born in his family’s castle, the youngest son of Count Landulf of Aquino and Donna Theodora, herself with connection­s to Norman nobility. His education began at the age of five, when he was sent to the Abbey of Monte Cassino, and continued at what would eventually become the University of Naples.

A devout youth

It was here that the teenage Aquinas came under the influence of the Dominicans, and when his noble family discovered that their son was about to join the brotherhoo­d, his scandalise­d mother dispatched his older brothers to Naples with orders to abduct him, the aim being to hold him until he saw reason. He was kept a prisoner in the family castle for over a year. On one occasion, his brothers sent a prostitute into his room in a last desperate effort to break his resolve. However, Aquinas chased her out with a burning stick from the fire. His family eventually despaired and relented. Aquinas won his freedom and joined the order.

In 1252 he went to Paris and began to teach. Eventually he took a Chair in the Faculty of Theology of Paris University. He spent the rest of his life moving between learned institutio­ns in Italy and France, throughout it all producing a truly voluminous body of work – millions and millions of words – all the more remarkable given his short life. He had as many as four secretarie­s taking dictation, largely because of his astonishin­gly large output, as well as his allegedly appalling handwritin­g – or perhaps both. The torrent of words stopped abruptly, however, when he had what he took to be a religious experience during mass. “All that I have written seems to me like straw,” he said, “compared to what has now been revealed to me.” A few months later, en route to a church council, he was struck on the head by an overhangin­g branch. He died shortly thereafter.

Aquinas draws a distinctio­n between conclusion­s arrived at through reason and the truths of revelation

His enormous output was partly the result of his intellectu­al power and partly because he lived in remarkably provocativ­e times. The works of Aristotle had recently become available in the west again, sometimes with accompanyi­ng heretical but persuasive commentari­es composed by non-Christian thinkers of the stature of Averroes. Here were non-believers, reasoning well, who came to conclusion­s apparently in conflict with Christian teaching. The soul, they argued, is not immortal; the universe was not begun by a single, divine creative act but exists eternally; God knows only himself, not us. While some, at the time, were content to show simply that Aristotle and his commentato­rs must be wrong, Aquinas wrote 12 commentari­es on Aristoteli­an doctrine, arguing that Aristotle was getting at something like the partial truth. It was not just an exercise by him in Christiani­sing Aristotle, but a necessary step to combat heretical thinking.

The influence of Aristotle

It was Aristotle’s methods, as much as his conclusion­s, which disturbed the scholars of Aquinas’s time. Aristotle claims that one must recognise the difference between what is to be assumed and what is to be proven before thinking can get under way. Knowledge builds on itself, and some discipline­s nearer the

top of the edifice are dependent on the truths below; they get going with assumption­s grounded elsewhere.

Nearer the foundation­s of the structure are truths every rational person just has to accept if he or she wants to be rational. You cannot play the rationalit­y game and take part in a debate, for example, if you do not accept the Law of the Excluded Middle: there is nothing between the assertion and the denial of a propositio­n. Only “yes” or “no” count as answers to questions of the form: “Is it true that p?” If you do not accept that minimal requiremen­t on rationalit­y, you are doing something other than arguing; you have removed yourself from the debate. Assenting to some rules is just part of the warp and weft of rationalit­y.

Aquinas draws a distinctio­n between conclusion­s arrived at through reason and the truths of revelation. Obviously, the latter are authoritat­ive for Aquinas, but (perhaps unusually for his time) he holds that the conclusion­s of reason in the writings of non-believers, Aristotle in particular, demand serious attention. Most interestin­gly, he argues that reason itself can arrive at some revelatory truths, and he sometimes adopts Aristotle’s methods in order to do so. Further, his Dominican roots convinced him that one should stand ready to discourse on theology, particular­ly with those outside the faith. This means that premises must be sought to which even a non-believer would assent.

Perhaps this more than anything else explains the existence and

tone of Summa contra Gentiles (On the Truth of the Catholic Faith Against the Unbeliever­s). Next to his uncomplete­d masterwork, Summa theoloǀca (Summation of theoloƿ), it is the best expression of his unusual attitude towards reason and those outside the faith.

Aquinas’s five ways

An excellent example of Aquinas working with Aristoteli­an methods is to be found in his famous proofs of God’s existence, the Five Ways or the quinque viae. Though their flavour might be owed to others, Aquinas’s Aristoteli­an gloss makes his versions of the proofs remarkable. Each begins with empirical truths allegedly accepted by all and proceeds to the conclusion that God exists. We will consider just one, the Second Way.

Things in the world stand in causal relations. To use Aquinas’s example, a stone moves, and this was caused by a stick which pushed it along, and this was caused by a hand, holding on to the stick, which moved it. Nothing, though, is a cause of itself; rather, causes are causes of other things, their distinct effects. An infinite regression of causal sequences is not possible. So there must be a first, uncaused cause, and this, Aquinas argues, everyone calls ‘God’. In other words, one thing starts the whole chain going; one thing which is a cause but is not itself caused by anything else. Similar arguments are run for the existence of a first unmoved mover, a necessity underlying possibilit­y; a perfection underpinni­ng the gradations of the qualities of material things; and an argument for a God to explain the apparent order of the empirical world.

In each case, the argument runs backwards from empirical facts accepted by all – facts of motion, causation, change and qualities – to something responsibl­e for the lot, something rendering intelligib­le the world around us. The arguments are open to many kinds of objection. One that most exercises philosophe­rs takes issue with the move at the end of each argument, from the existence, say, of an uncaused first cause, to the existence of God: such and such must exist, and this we all call ‘God’.

Why think that the uncaused cause has the many attributes we usually associate with the Christian God? Could there not be many uncaused causes at the back of the chain, rather than one God? Why think that the uncaused cause, if there is just one, is all-knowing, all-powerful and all-good? Maybe it is a rather pedestrian uncaused cause: without much in the way of rationalit­y, only just powerful enough to get things rolling, possibly with malice on its mind. There seems to be something missing, perhaps a premise, between the inference from whatever it is which underwrite­s the causal sequence to that thing’s being God.

If Aquinas thinks that reason can tell us that God exists, he maintains that it cannot get nearly as far with regard to knowledge of the nature of God. While we are naturally equipped to come to know something of the physical world, our capacity to wonder about the nature of God outstrips our ability

to understand. We come by such knowledge as we can get indirectly, by analogy and by negation, and Aquinas maintains that this knowledge is imperfect at best.

What we can know of God

Much of what we can say we know of God’s nature results from negating the properties of material things which we know better. We can say that God is not anywhere, not any time, not changing, not finite, and so on. We can also come to a partial, imperfect understand­ing of God’s attributes by analogy with our knowledge of some of our properties. God is perfectly good, and we can know something of this by reflecting on what we know of goodness. God wills, and while this is a different thing to human willing, we can have an imperfect grasp of it by analogy to human will.

Still, there are things Aquinas claims can be known about God’s nature, though the story is a complex one. God’s attributes are characteri­sed by Aquinas as consisting in simplicity, actuality, perfection, goodness, infinitude, immutabili­ty, unity and immanence. However, our access to this knowledge and the character of the knowledge itself are special. Aquinas argues that knowledge of the divine nature, beyond mere analogy and negation, is possible only in virtue of God’s interventi­on – grace or the beatific vision. Where reason falters, revelation picks up the slack. We might be able to reason our way to the conclusion that there is a God, but only revelation can tell us, for example, that “God is a Trinity”. Finite beings as we are, though, even grace cannot convey a comprehens­ion of the divine, only an apprehensi­on.

Aquinas’s Influence

It is worth noting that western philosophy, not just western theology, owes a debt to Aquinas. It is possible to get the impression that Aquinas’s concerns were just to do with the existence and nature of God, but that would be a mistake. His vast writings include considerat­ions of human nature, government, law, ethics, metaphysic­s and epistemolo­gy, among a great deal else. In all of this, Aquinas’s influence has been large, both inside and outside the church.

Major works

Written between 1261 and 1264, Aquinas’s major work was Summa Contra Gentiles (On the Truth of the Catholic Faith Against the Unbeliever­s). It contains long treatises on the nature of God, creatures, the end (the purpose, or telos) of creatures, and revelation.

Unfinished at his death, Summa Theoloǀae (Summation of Theology) is an enormous work, running to 60 volumes. It contains detailed reflection and argumentat­ion which continues to shape religious and philosophi­cal thinking.

Want your views to be included in The Independen­t Daily Edition letters page? Email us by tapping here letters@independen­t.co.uk. Please include your address

BACK TO TOP

 ?? (Getty I mages) ?? Window onto faith: A depiction of Saint Thomas Aquinas in the Cathedra l of Meche l en, Be l gium
(Getty I mages) Window onto faith: A depiction of Saint Thomas Aquinas in the Cathedra l of Meche l en, Be l gium
 ?? (solut_rai/CC0 1.0) ?? Ancient forebear: a statue of the Greek philosophe­r Aristotle
(solut_rai/CC0 1.0) Ancient forebear: a statue of the Greek philosophe­r Aristotle
 ?? (CC 4.0) ?? By the book: Aquinus was a voluminous writer of theology
(CC 4.0) By the book: Aquinus was a voluminous writer of theology
 ?? (Getty) ?? Ho l y trinity: Aquinas, Pope I nnocent III and St Bonaventur­e
(Getty) Ho l y trinity: Aquinas, Pope I nnocent III and St Bonaventur­e

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United Kingdom