The Independent

PRODIGIOUS PASCAL

A polymath of so many talents, it was reported that even the great René Descartes was envious of the Frenchman

- Want your views to be included in The Independen­t Daily Edition letters page? Email us by tapping here letters@independen­t.co.uk. Please include your address

Blaise Pascal (1623–62) was a man of many talents. In his short life, he made significan­t contributi­ons to the fields of philosophy, mathematic­s, physics and theology. When not working on the mysteries of the universe, Pascal also found time

to invent a calculatin­g machine and to establish an omnibus system in Paris (the profits of which went to the poor), and this from a man who died before his 40th birthday. He is generally considered to have been one of the 17th-century’s best intellects; indeed, many commentato­rs report that even the great philosophe­r René Descartes was envious of Pascal’s prodigious abilities.

It was clear from a very early age that Pascal was going to be something special. His father Étienne, a trained lawyer and brilliant mathematic­ian, with connection­s to some of the leading scientific thinkers of the age via his associatio­n with the Mersenne circle of natural philosophe­rs, took on the task of his son’s education. Blaise was extraordin­arily precocious. His sister reports, for example, that by the age of 12 he had managed to work out Pythagoras’s Theorem on his own. His father recognised his talent for mathematic­s and began to teach him. It was not long before Pascal was participat­ing on his own terms in the discussion­s of the Mersenne group.

His calculatin­g machine was a product of these early years. His father was working as Rouen’s chief tax officer, a job which involved many routine, but time-consuming calculatio­ns. Pascal’s machine, with its ability to manipulate numbers of up to six figures, was designed to remove some of the drudgery from the work. Although it proved to be too expensive to make to be a commercial success, it worked correctly, and it is generally considered to be the world’s first geared computer.

Thoughts on vacuum

Also at this time, Pascal was engaged in the scientific work which was to make his internatio­nal reputation. He had become interested in a set of experiment­s by the Italian physicist Evangelist­a Torricelli, which showed that when a tube of mercury was placed upside-down in a basin of mercury, a gap appeared at the top of the tube. The issue under debate had to do with what was in the gap. Traditiona­l, scholastic thinkers, remaining true to the Aristoteli­an adage that nature abhors a vacuum, held that the tube contained some kind of subtle, invisible substance. Pascal’s view was that such matters could

not be decided by an appeal to authority, and, with Pierre Petit, he embarked on a series of experiment­s to determine the truth of the matter.

Pascal employed a striking image to press this point home. He likened the learning of all men – in other words, scientific progress – to the learning of one immortal man over time

In 1647, after some four years of experiment­ation, he published his Experiment­s on a Vacuum. In it, though he shied away from claiming definitive­ly that the tube contained a vacuum, he outlined in some detail why the idea that the gap comprised a subtle substance was flawed. This provoked a response from Père Noël, the rector of the Jesuit Collège de Clermont in Paris, who remained committed to the traditiona­l Aristoteli­an view. In his reply, Pascal set down what he considered to be the principles of scientific methodolog­y, and in a move which in a way anticipate­d 20th-century logical positivism, accused Noël of the invention, ex nihilo, of a substance which was, in principle, undetectab­le:

If one asks them, or you, to make us see this matter, they reply that it is not visible. If one asks that it make some sound, they say that it cannot be heard, and likewise for all the other senses. Thus they think that they have achieved much by making others incapable of showing that subtle matter does not exist, thereby depriving themselves of any chance of showing that it does exist. But we find more reason to deny its existence because it cannot be proved, than

to believe in it for the sole reason that one cannot prove that it does not exist. Pascal further developed his thoughts on scientific methodolog­y in his Preface to a treatise on a vacuum, which he wrote just a few years after his exchange of letters with Father Noël. In this, as well as reiteratin­g his belief that appeals to authoritat­ive texts and the like have no place in scientific reasoning, he outlined his view of science as a progressiv­e enterprise, with new generation­s of scientists building on the knowledge handed down to them by their predecesso­rs:

The secrets of nature are concealed; although she is continuall­y working, we do not always discover her effects: time reveals them from age to age, and although always alike in herself she is not always alike known. The experiment­s that ǀve us the knowledge of these secrets are multiplied continuall­y … It is in this manner that we may at the present day adopt different sentiments and new opinions, without despising the ancients and without ingratitud­e, since the first knowledge which they have ǀven us has served as a stepping-stone to our own …

Pascal employed a striking image to press this point home. He likened the learning of all men – in other words, scientific progress – to the learning of one immortal man over time. Learning is cumulative, and, in scientific terms, the ancients, our ancestors, were in their infancy. Moreover, it is fair to suppose that if the scientists of the past were privy to what we now know, they too would reassess commitment­s which were then held to be inviolate.

However, Pascal did not entirely rule out a role for authority in the quest for knowledge, for when it comes to theology, different rules come into play. In fact, according to Pascal, authority is the only measure of truth in theologica­l matters; when we want to know about a realm which is beyond the reach

of reason, then we have little choice but to rely on the authority of sacred texts.

Pascal’s conversion

This might seem a rather strange idea to be held by someone so committed to reason and evidence in the pursuit of scientific knowledge. However, Pascal, certainly in the latter part of his life, was a deeply religious man. Indeed, on the night of 23 November 1654, at the age of 31, he underwent what might be called a conversion experience; it was sufficient­ly profound that he recorded it on a piece of parchment, which he then had sewn into his jacket, and which he carried with him for the rest of his life.

After this experience, Pascal turned increasing­ly to writing on religious matters. His Lettres Provincial­es, a series of 18 letters, published in 1656–7, was a scathing attack on the views of the Jesuits. In essence, he accused them of expediency in their theologica­l and moral outlook; they were, he claimed, willing to sacrifice doctrinal accuracy for the purposes of political gain. The context of this dispute was a conflict between Jansenism, an approach to Christiani­ty rooted in a strict interpreta­tion of the ideas of Augustine, and the wider Catholic Church. By the time of the Lettres, Pascal was a committed Jansenist; and his interventi­on in the dispute was an attempt to shore up support for Jansenism in the face of papal censure.

Pascal’s wider theologica­l views showed very clearly the influence of Augustine. He was committed to the Augustinia­n idea that the fall of man had left human beings spirituall­y corrupt to the core. It is only by the grace of God that people – and by no means all people – can be redeemed; in his view, God’s grace is such that those people he had blessed will always choose to follow his path. However, as a good Augustinia­n, Pascal was also committed to the idea of predestina­tion, that is, the idea that salvation is preordaine­d. Therefore, there is nothing specifical­ly that the individual can do to attain salvation; either God will make his presence felt in the heart of a particular individual, or he won’t.

Pascal’s wager

This belief makes it slightly paradoxica­l that Pascal spent the final years of his life putting together the beginnings of an apologia for Christiani­ty. Although it was never fully completed, the extant material was pieced together as Pensées. It is in this work that one finds Pascal’s famous wager. The argument is as follows: either God exists or he does not. We have to choose one way or the other on this issue; it is an unavoidabl­e existentia­l dilemma. If God does not exist, then we lose very little by believing that he does exist. If he does exist, then we stand to gain an awful lot by believing that he does, and to lose an awful lot by thinking that he doesn’t. Therefore, it is sensible to wager that he does exist, and to behave appropriat­ely. As Pascal put it: “I should be much more afraid of being mistaken and then finding out that Christiani­ty is true than of being mistaken in believing it to be true.”

The wager, then, is not an argument for the existence of God; Pascal was aware that he could not convince unbeliever­s of God’s existence by rational argument. It is, rather, an argument for the rationalit­y of belief in God. It was aimed not so much at people who were convinced that God did not exist, but rather at the waverers, people who were sceptical but interested. It does, however, sit uneasily with his Augustinia­n view of predestina­tion. Pascal anticipate­d the criticism that the idea of trying to persuade people of the efficacy of religious belief is

strange if it is true their belief is not constituti­ve of salvation. His response was that God might choose to do his work through other people, so it was his duty to attempt to bring people to faith. However, while this response might explain Pascal’s motives, it isn’t clear that Pascal’s wager can function as a motive to action. If a person’s future is predestine­d, why do anything? Why not just sit back and wait for God to act?

Despite this difficulty, the wager has remained an influentia­l argument. It is seen as an early example of decision theory. Indeed, it is fair to say that among the educated public it is what Pascal is best known for. However, in a sense this is unfortunat­e;

Pascal’s reach was broad, and in 21st-century terms his scientific and mathematic­al work is perhaps more impressive than his religious apologetic­s.

Major works

Experiment­s on a Vacuum (1647)

Based on four years experiment­al research, this work argues against the traditiona­l view that “nature abhors a vacuum”.

Provincial Letters (1657)

A series of 18 letters, which amount to a scathing attack on the views of the Jesuits. In essence, they are accused of expediency in their theologica­l and moral outlook, willing to sacrifice doctrinal accuracy for the purposes of political gain.

Thoughts (or Pensées) (1670)

An apologia for Christiani­ty. Unfinished at Pascal’s death, this work comprises a series of short essays and aphorisms. It is best known for featuring Pascal’s famous wager (”Pascal’s Wager”), an argument for the rationalit­y of a belief in God.

BACK TO TOP

 ?? (Getty) ?? Pasca l identified the vacuum and offered a rationa l argument for be l ieving in God
(Getty) Pasca l identified the vacuum and offered a rationa l argument for be l ieving in God
 ?? (Getty) ?? Learning is cumu l ative and, in scientific terms, the ancients, our ancestors, were in their infancy, be l ieved Pasca l
(Getty) Learning is cumu l ative and, in scientific terms, the ancients, our ancestors, were in their infancy, be l ieved Pasca l
 ?? (Getty/iStock) ?? Pascal spent the fina l years of his l ife putting together the beginnings of an apologia for Christiani­ty
(Getty/iStock) Pascal spent the fina l years of his l ife putting together the beginnings of an apologia for Christiani­ty
 ?? (AFP via Getty) ?? Pascal’s statue under the Saint -Jacques tower in Paris
(AFP via Getty) Pascal’s statue under the Saint -Jacques tower in Paris

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United Kingdom