Chattanooga Times Free Press

DISCRIMINA­TION AND PREJUDICE

- Creators.com

Some of the confusion in thinking about matters of race stems from an ambiguity in terms. I am going to take a stab at suggesting operationa­l definition­s for a couple of terms in our discussion of race. Good analytical thinking requires we do not confuse one behavioral phenomenon with another.

Let’s start with “discrimina­tion.” Discrimina­tion is the act of choice, and choice is a necessary fact of life. Our lives are spent discrimina­ting for or against different activities and people. Some students discrimina­te against George Mason University in favor of attending Temple University. Many people racially discrimina­te by marrying within their own race rather than seeking partners of other races. People discrimina­te in many ways in forming contracts and other interrelat­ionships. In each case, one person is benefited by discrimina­tion; another is harmed or has reduced opportunit­ies.

What about prejudice? Prejudice is a useful term that is often misused. Its Latin root is praejudici­um, meaning “an opinion or judgment formed … without due examinatio­n.” Thus, we might define a prejudicia­l act as one where a decision is made on the basis of incomplete informatio­n. The decision-maker might use stereotype­s as a substitute for that informatio­n.

Here is a simple yet intuitivel­y appealing example. When you open your front door, you are greeted by a full-grown tiger. The uninterest­ing prediction is that the average person would leave the area in great dispatch. Why he would do so is more interestin­g. It is unlikely the person’s fear and decision to seek safety is based on any detailed informatio­n held about that particular tiger. More likely, his decision to seek safety is based on tiger folklore, what he has been told about tigers or how he has seen other tigers behave. He prejudges that tiger. He uses tiger stereotype­s.

If a person did not prejudge that tiger, he would endeavor to seek more informatio­n prior to his decision to run. He might attempt to pet the tiger, talk to him and seek safety only if the tiger were menacing. The average person probably would not choose that strategy. He would surmise the expected cost of getting more informatio­n about the tiger is greater than the expected benefit. He would probably conclude, “All I need to know is he’s a tiger, and he’s probably like the rest of them.” But there’s no way one can say unambiguou­sly whether the person likes or dislikes tigers.

Similarly, the cheaply observed fact an individual is short, an amputee, Black, or a woman provides what some people deem sufficient informatio­n for decision-making. For example, if asked to identify individual­s with doctorate degrees in physics only by observing race and sex, most of us would assign a higher probabilit­y that white or Asian men would have such degrees than Black men or women. Suppose you are a police chief and you’re trying to find the culprits breaking into cars, would you spend any of your resources investigat­ing people in senior citizen homes? Using an observable attribute as a proxy for an unobservab­le attribute lies at the heart of decision theory.

Lastly, is there a moral dimension to discrimina­tion and prejudice? Should one be indifferen­t about whether he attends Temple or George Mason and thus makes his decision by flipping a coin? Is it more righteous to use the same technique when choosing to marry within or outside his race? Is it morally superior to be indifferen­t with respect to race in marriage, employment and socializin­g? Can one make a rigorous moral case for government coercion to determine whether one attends Temple or George Mason, marries outside his race, or is indifferen­t about the racial characteri­stics of whom he employs?

 ??  ?? Walter Williams
Walter Williams

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States