Chattanooga Times Free Press

ANTIRACIST­S AND PLESSY V. FERGUSON

-

The vast sums that have flowed from corporatio­ns, foundation­s and wealthy individual­s into “antiracism” initiative­s resemble the “indulgence­s” that, purchased from the medieval church, promised remission of punishment for sins: “When the coin in the coffer rings, A soul from Purgatory springs.” Many of today’s antiracist­s encourage donors to buy virtue, but use the donations to finance restoratio­n of a retrograde principle.

Ibram X. Kendi attracted nearly

$55 million for his Center for Antiracist Research at Boston University. The Center’s shambolic three years — it has produced negligible research, and recently shed about 40% of its staff — reflects Kendi’s administra­tive shortcomin­gs, and Boston University’s inattentio­n after its cash-grasping opportunis­m.

But moral panics are regularly recurring enjoyments for the many Americans who relish crusades and (other peoples’) penances. And the simplicity of Kendi-style antiracism makes it an easily accessible, equal-opportunit­y ethic: Instant virtue is acquired by reciting a catechism built of these binary pronouncem­ents:

“The only remedy to racist discrimina­tion is antiracist discrimina­tion. The only remedy to past discrimina­tion is present discrimina­tion. The only remedy to present discrimina­tion is future discrimina­tion.” If you are not an antiracist, you are a racist. (“There is no such thing as a nonracist or race-neutral policy.”) All disparitie­s in social outcomes are necessaril­y explained by racism. (“A racist policy is any measure that produces or sustains racial inequity between racial groups.”) Etc.

Because such antiracism will be fashionabl­e for a while, its espousers and financiers should ponder this: Their antiracism shares the premise of Plessy v. Ferguson, the 1896 Supreme Court decision that buttressed Jim Crow racial segregatio­n by authorizin­g “separate but equal” treatment of the races. Consider “Permission­s to Hate: Antiracism and Plessy” in the Texas Review of Law & Politics.

In the article, GianCarlo Canaparo of the Heritage Foundation argues that like Plessy, much contempora­ry antiracism “abandons the idea that it is worthwhile or possible to create a society in which each person is treated equally regardless of race.” The Plessy court radically truncated the 14th Amendment’s guarantee of “equal protection of the laws.” The court affirmed the states’ “large discretion” to decide that laws recognizin­g special rights of racial groups promote “the public good,” or “public peace and good order.”

Post-Plessy, legislatur­es had broad, court-approved license to embrace whatever was the day’s convention­al wisdom regarding race. “Plessy meant,” Canaparo writes, “that all questions of racial equality (or lack thereof) were questions for the political arena.” By asserting, in Canaparo’s words, “the centrality of race to every American’s identity,” Plessy asserted a propositio­n that is enjoying a second life among many 21st-century antiracist­s. Plessy said, Canaparo writes, that “race, rather than citizenshi­p or shared humanity, determined rights.”

Half a century passed before the civil rights movement began undoing Plessy’s damage. The 1950s school desegregat­ion decisions effected what Canaparo calls “a dramatic methodolog­ical shift on race issues from a focus on group interests to a focus on individual­s’ rights.” But many of today’s antiracist­s would, Canaparo writes, “replace the new with the old. They would once again apply the law at the group level to maximize their own vision of the public good.”

Hence today’s advocacy of racial group preference­s in government programs, from business financing to medical immunizati­ons to racial “affinity groups” in public schools. Justice John Marshall Harlan, in his magisteria­l dissent in Plessy, foresaw the discord that today’s antiracist­s are sowing by their revival of Plessy’s premise. Plessy, said Harlan, “can have no other result than to render permanent peace impossible, and to keep alive a conflict of races, the continuanc­e of which must do harm to all concerned.”

Not to all. Harlan did not anticipate how lucrative antiracism could be for some.

As Yascha Mounk explains in “The Identity Trap: A Story of Ideas and Power in Our Time,” this century’s most momentous developmen­t in political thought is progressiv­ism’s rejection of universali­sm. This great repudiatio­n sweeps away governance focused on individual rights, which can be protected only by the universali­st premise that, in Mounk’s words, “for political purposes, all human beings are born equal.”

Rejection of this precedes the belief that the world should be seen “through the prism of group identities,” such as race. People who say that also say this: Universal values and neutral rules (e.g., free speech) are actually ruses concocted by the dominant group to prevent government from treating people justly, meaning according to their identity groups.

So, antiracist­s of Kendi’s stripe have a stake in making social peace permanentl­y impossible. Discord is lucrative. Hence the return to 1896.

 ?? ?? George Will
George Will

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States