Los Angeles Times (Sunday)

What the ancient Greeks got about democracy that Trump does not

- By Jane Manners and Melissa Lane Jane Manners is an assistant professor at the Beasley School of Law of Temple University. Melissa Lane is a professor of politics at Princeton.

President Trump recently scored a victory with the Supreme Court: The justices agreed to hear his case that his former role as president grants him immunity in the face of federal charges. Among the central questions in this criminal case: What does it mean for the president to “take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed,” as the Constituti­on requires?

Trump and his lawyers have argued that this constituti­onal clause grants him near-total immunity from judicial oversight, as opposed to being an accountabi­lity measure meant to hold the president responsibl­e for enforcing the laws. While commentato­rs on both sides have focused on what it means to “faithfully execute” the laws, few consider as closely the clause’s other phrase: the exhortatio­n to “take care.”

A common reading of that phrase by legal scholars is that it simply means to “ensure,” as in to “ensure that the Laws be faithfully executed.” But that reading shortchang­es centuries of political thought about a question that hangs over Trump’s prosecutio­n, and the outcome of this year’s election: What does it mean for public officials to have a duty of care?

That question was taken seriously in ancient Athens, where a 403 BC decree instructed one of the traditiona­l governing councils, known as the Council of the Areopagus, to “Take caring charge of the laws, so that the office holders may employ the laws that have been passed.” The similarity to what’s in the Constituti­on is striking: Both speak of caring and link it to the laws’ execution.

Yet the Athenian instructio­n more explicitly references “caring ” in the sense of being a caretaker or guardian. This suggests that the officials’ duty is not simply to ensure the laws are executed, but also to safeguard their spirit. To execute without caring, indifferen­t to the fate of the overall democratic system, is to fail to execute properly at all.

In the 18th century American context, such ideas also had resonance, as shown in debates over the Constituti­on’s ratificati­on. Commentato­rs in the government and media spoke of federal officehold­ers’ “public trust,” their role as “servants” or “confidenti­al guardians” of the people, and of the president as the “supreme conservato­r of the laws.”

Even the president’s constituti­onally mandated oath to “preserve, protect and defend the Constituti­on” invokes a notion of guardiansh­ip, an idea of rule that goes well beyond the idea that the president is merely the nation’s chief executive (or faithful executor).

To safeguard the spirit of the laws, one has to know the laws’ purpose (in Greek, their telos). That telos is broadly understood in ancient Greek texts to be the good of the people. Accordingl­y, officials were described as stewards and guardians — in the poetry of Pindar, the comedies of Aristophan­es and the oratory of Isocrates, among the works of other authors. These portrayals related to the roles of household stewards and legal guardians of children. As with legal guardians today, officials’ duty was to exercise their powers to care for the good of others.

The ancient Athenian philosophe­r Plato identified caring as a fundamenta­l dimension of statecraft in his text “Statesman.” He argued in “Laws” that a good constituti­on requires a body similar to the Council of the Areopagus that can “keep watch over the laws.”

Even in his dialogue “Republic,” rather than arguing for untrammele­d rule by philosophe­rs as many have thought, he proposed that a group of senior guardians should educate, select and supervise officehold­ers (and that the guardians should themselves be tested and selected by their predecesso­rs).

This is constituti­onal rule, as suggested by the dialogue’s title in Greek (Politeia, literally meaning “Constituti­on”), in which no individual official is immune to scrutiny as to whether they are taking proper care.

What might the U.S. learn from these ancient ideas? For starters, we might recognize that our own founding documents suggest that the telos of our democracy is, as it was for the Greeks, the good of the people.

Imagine, then, if we establishe­d our own group of senior guardians to weigh in on the suitabilit­y of presidenti­al candidates to perform the role’s essential caring function. The group could include living past presidents, who know from experience what the role requires, and, if necessary to make up a quorum, other qualified retired public officials.

Just as the American Bar Assn. rates federal judicial nominees as “well qualified,” “qualified” or “not qualified,” this body could rate major party presidenti­al candidates on the basis of transparen­t, preselecte­d and nonpartisa­n criteria. Although such a council would have no official role in the electoral process, its rating would signal the deliberati­ve judgment of a uniquely expert group of individual­s.

Moreover, in screening potential members for its own ranks, a council of ex-presidents could send further messages about the conduct of past executives.

Just as Plato’s guardians were tested and selected by other guardians, so too could this group self-police, determinin­g membership based on factors including performanc­e before, in and after office in terms of exhibiting appropriat­e care — or a lack thereof — for the health of the democratic process and constituti­onal system. Exclusion from membership might bear on the National Archives’ support for a presidenti­al library and other honors convention­ally bestowed on past presidents.

To be sure, such a council would be subject to the full range of human foibles and moral failures — at least a dozen U.S. presidents, after all, were or had been slaveholde­rs — and voters may well disregard their judgments. And it perhaps sounds like a flight of fancy to propose a new functional cooperativ­e body in this fractious era of American governance.

On the other hand, the collective experience of prior officehold­ers may be exactly what we need to safeguard the president’s constituti­onal duty to take due care. Their ratings would remind all Americans of a lesson that the ancient Greeks recognized: that caring is fundamenta­l to ruling.

For starters, we might recognize that our own founding documents suggest that the telos of our democracy is, as it was for the Greeks, the good of the people.

 ?? Photo illustrati­on by Jim Cooke Los Angeles Times; photograph­s via Getty Images ?? Of Rule and Office: Plato’s Ideas of the Political by Melissa Lane
Photo illustrati­on by Jim Cooke Los Angeles Times; photograph­s via Getty Images Of Rule and Office: Plato’s Ideas of the Political by Melissa Lane

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States