The New York Review of Books

David Cole

Why We Must Still Defend Free Speech

- *The leading collection of essays advancing this critique is Mari J. Matsuda, Charles R. Lawrence III, Richard Delgado, and Kimberlé Williams Crenshaw, Words that Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment (Westview, 1993). Fo

Does the First Amendment need a rewrite in the era of Donald Trump? Should the rise of white supremacis­t and neo-Nazi groups lead us to cut back the protection afforded to speech that expresses hatred and advocates violence, or otherwise undermines equality? If free speech exacerbate­s inequality, why doesn’t equality, also protected by the Constituti­on, take precedence?

After the tragic violence at a white supremacis­t rally in Charlottes­ville, Virginia, on August 12, these questions take on renewed urgency. Many have asked in particular why the ACLU, of which I am national legal director, represente­d Jason Kessler, the organizer of the rally, in challengin­g Charlottes­ville’s last-minute effort to revoke his permit. The city proposed to move his rally a mile from its originally approved site—Emancipati­on Park, the location of the Robert E. Lee monument whose removal Kessler sought to protest—but offered no reason why the protest would be any easier to manage a mile away. As ACLU offices across the country have done for thousands of marchers for almost a century, the ACLU of Virginia gave Kessler legal help to preserve his permit. Should the fatal violence that followed prompt recalibrat­ion of the scope of free speech? The future of the First Amendment may be at issue. A 2015 Pew Research Center poll reported that 40 percent of millennial­s think the government should be able to suppress speech deemed offensive to minority groups, as compared to only 12 percent of those born between 1928 and 1945. Young people today voice far less faith in free speech than do their grandparen­ts. And Europe, where racist speech is not protected, has shown that democracie­s can reasonably differ about this issue. People who oppose the protection of racist speech make several arguments, all ultimately resting on a claim that speech rights conflict with equality, and that equality should prevail in the balance.* They contend that the “marketplac­e of ideas” assumes a mythical level playing field. If some speakers drown out or silence others, the marketplac­e cannot function in the interests of all. They argue that the history of mob and state violence targeting African-Americans makes racist speech directed at them especially indefensib­le. Tolerating such speech reinforces harms that this nation has done to African-Americans from slavery through Jim Crow to today’s de facto segregatio­n, implicit bias, and structural discrimina­tion. And still others argue that while it might have made sense to tolerate Nazis marching in Skokie in 1978, now, when white supremacis­ts have a friend in the president himself, the power and influence they wield justify a different approach. There is truth in each of these propositio­ns. The United States is a profoundly unequal society. Our nation’s historical mistreatme­nt of AfricanAme­ricans has been shameful and the scourge of racism persists to this day. Racist speech causes real harm. It can inspire violence and intimidate people from freely exercising their own rights. There is no doubt that Donald Trump’s appeals to white resentment and his reluctance to condemn white supremacis­ts after Charlottes­ville have emboldened many racists. But at least in the public arena, none of these unfortunat­e truths supports authorizin­g the state to suppress speech that advocates ideas antithetic­al to egalitaria­n values.

The argument that free speech should not be protected in conditions of inequality is misguided. The right to free speech does not rest on the presumptio­n of a level playing field. Virtually all rights—speech included—are enjoyed unequally, and can reinforce inequality. The right to property most obviously protects the billionair­e more than it does the poor. Homeowners have greater privacy rights than apartment dwellers, who in turn have more privacy than the homeless. The fundamenta­l right to choose how to educate one’s children means little to parents who cannot afford private schools, and contribute­s to the resilience of segregated schools and the reproducti­on of privilege. Criminal defendants’ rights are enjoyed much more robustly by those who can afford to hire an expensive lawyer than by those dependent on the meager resources that states dedicate to the defense of the indigent, thereby contributi­ng to the endemic disparitie­s that plague our criminal justice system. Critics argue that the First Amendment is different, because if the weak are silenced while the strong speak, or if some have more to spend on speech than others, the outcomes of the “marketplac­e of ideas” will be skewed. But the marketplac­e is a metaphor; it describes not a scientific method for identifyin­g truth but a choice among realistic options. It maintains only that it is better for the state to remain neutral than to dictate what is true and suppress the rest. One can be justifiabl­y skeptical of a debate in which Charles Koch or George Soros has outsized advantages over everyone else, but still prefer it to one in which the Trump— or indeed Obama—administra­tion can control what can be said. If free speech is critical to democracy and to holding our representa­tives accountabl­e—and it is—we cannot allow our representa­tives to suppress views they think are wrong, false, or disruptive.

Should our nation’s shameful history of racism change the equation? There is no doubt that African-Americans have suffered unique mistreatme­nt, and that our country has yet to reckon adequately with that fact. But to treat speech targeting African-Americans differentl­y from speech targeting anyone else cannot be squared with the first principle of free speech: the state must be neutral with regard to speakers’ viewpoints. Moreover, what about other groups? While each group’s experience­s are distinct, many have suffered grave discrimina­tion, including Native Americans, Asian-Americans, LGBT people, women, Jews, Latinos, Muslims, and immigrants generally. Should government officials be free to censor speech that offends or targets any of these groups? If not all, which groups get special protection?

And even if we could somehow answer that question, how would we define what speech to suppress? Should the government be able to silence all arguments against affirmativ­e action or about genetic difference­s between men and women, or just uneducated racist and sexist rants? It is easy to recognize inequality; it is virtually impossible to articulate a standard for suppressio­n of speech that would not afford government officials dangerousl­y broad discretion and invite discrimina­tion against particular viewpoints.

But are these challenges perhaps worth taking on because Donald Trump is president, and his victory has given new voice to white supremacis­ts? That is exactly the wrong conclusion. After all, if we were to authorize government officials to suppress speech they find contrary to American values, it would be Trump—and his allies in state and local government­s—who would use that power. Here is the ultimate contradict­ion in the argument for state suppressio­n of speech in the name of equality: it demands protection of disadvanta­ged minorities’ interests, but in a democracy, the state acts in the name of the majority, not the minority. Why would disadvanta­ged minorities trust representa­tives of the majority to decide whose speech should be censored? At one time, most Americans embraced “separate but equal” for the races and separate spheres for the sexes as defining equality. It was the freedom to contest those views, safeguarde­d by the principle of free speech, that allowed us to reject them.

As Frederick Douglass reminded us, “Power concedes nothing without a demand. It never did and it never will.” Throughout our history, disadvanta­ged minority groups have effectivel­y used the First Amendment to speak, associate, and assemble for the purpose of demanding their rights—and the ACLU has defended their right to do so. Where would the movements for racial justice, women’s rights, and LGBT equality be without a muscular First Amendment?

In some limited but important settings, equality norms do trump free speech. At schools and in the workplace, for example, antidiscri­mination law forbids harassment and hostile working conditions based on race or sex, and those rules limit what people can say there. The courts have recognized that in situations involving formal hierarchy and captive audiences, speech can be limited to ensure equal access and treatment. But those exceptions do not extend to the public sphere, where ideas must be open to full and free contestati­on, and those who disagree can turn away or talk back.

The response to Charlottes­ville showed the power of talking back. When Donald Trump implied a kind of moral equivalenc­e between the white supremacis­t protesters and their counterpro­testers, he quickly found himself isolated. Prominent Republican­s, military leaders, business executives, and conservati­ve, moderate, and liberal commentato­rs alike condemned the ideology of white supremacy, Trump himself, or both.

When white supremacis­ts called a rally the following week in Boston, they mustered only a handful of

supporters. They were vastly outnumbere­d by tens of thousands of counterpro­testers who peacefully marched through the streets to condemn white supremacy, racism, and hate. Boston proved yet again that the most powerful response to speech that we hate is not suppressio­n but more speech. Even Stephen Bannon, until recently Trump’s chief strategist and now once again executive chairman of Breitbart News, denounced white supremacis­ts as “losers” and “a collection of clowns.” Free speech, in short, is exposing white supremacis­ts’ ideas to the condemnati­on they deserve. Moral condemnati­on, not legal suppressio­n, is the appropriat­e response to these despicable ideas.

Some white supremacis­ts advocate not only hate but violence. They want to purge the country of nonwhites, nonChristi­ans, and other “undesirabl­es,” and return us to a racial caste society— and the only way to do that is through force. The First Amendment protects speech but not violence. So what possible value is there in protecting speech advocating violence? Our history illustrate­s that unless very narrowly constraine­d, the power to restrict the advocacy of violence is an invitation to punish political dissent. A. Mitchell Palmer, J. Edgar Hoover, and Joseph McCarthy all used the advocacy of violence as a justificat­ion to punish people who associated with Communists, socialists, or civil rights groups.

Those lessons led the Supreme Court, in a 1969 ACLU case involving a Ku Klux Klan rally, to rule that speech advocating violence or other criminal conduct is protected unless it is intended and likely to produce imminent lawless action, a highly speech-protective rule. In addition to incitement, thus narrowly defined, a “true threat” against specific individual­s is also not protected. But aside from these instances in which speech and violence are inextricab­ly intertwine­d, speech advocating violence gets full First Amendment protection. In Charlottes­ville, the ACLU’s client swore under oath that he intended only a peaceful protest. The city cited general concerns about managing the crowd in seeking to move the marchers a mile from the originally approved site. But as the district court found, the city offered no reason why there wouldn’t be just as many protesters and counterpro­testers at the alternativ­e site. Violence did break out in Charlottes­ville, but that appears to have been at least in part because the police utterly failed to keep the protesters separated or to break up the fights.

What about speech and weapons? The ACLU’s executive director, Anthony Romero, explained that, in light of Charlottes­ville and the risk of violence at future protests, the ACLU will not represent marchers who seek to brandish weapons while protesting. (This is not a new position. In a pamphlet signed by Roger Baldwin, Arthur Garfield Hays, Morris Ernst, and others, the ACLU took a similar stance in 1934, explaining that we defended the Nazis’ right to speak, but not to march while armed.) This is a content-neutral policy; it applies to all armed marchers, regardless of their views. And it is driven by the twin concerns of avoiding violence and the impairment of many rights, speech included, that violence so often occasions. Free speech allows us to resolve our difference­s through public reason; violence is its antithesis. The First Amendment protects the exchange of views, not the exchange of bullets. Just as it is reasonable to exclude weapons from courthouse­s, airports, schools, and Fourth of July celebratio­ns on the National Mall, so it is reasonable to exclude them from public protests.

Some

ACLU staff and supporters have made a more limited argument. They don’t directly question whether the First Amendment should protect white supremacis­t groups. Instead, they ask why the ACLU as an organizati­on represents them. In most cases, the protesters should be able to find lawyers elsewhere. Many ACLU staff members understand­ably find representi­ng these groups repugnant; their views are directly contrary to many of the values we fight for. And representi­ng rightwing extremists makes it more difficult for the ACLU to work with its allies on a wide range of issues, from racial justice to LGBT equality to immigrants’ rights. As a matter of resources, the ACLU spends far more on claims to equality by marginaliz­ed groups than it does on First Amendment claims. If the First Amendment work is underminin­g our other efforts, why do it?

These are real costs, and deserve considerat­ion as ACLU lawyers make caseby-case decisions about how to deploy our resources. But they cannot be a bar to doing such work. The truth is that both internally and externally, it would be much easier for the ACLU to represent only those with whom we agree. But the power of our First Amendment advocacy turns on our commitment to a principle of viewpoint neutrality that requires protection for proponents and opponents of our own best view of racial justice. If we defended speech only when we agreed with it, on what ground would we ask others to tolerate speech they oppose?

In a fundamenta­l sense, the First Amendment safeguards not only the American experiment in democratic pluralism, but everything the ACLU does. In the pursuit of liberty and justice, we associate, advocate, and petition the government. We protect the First Amendment not only because it is the lifeblood of democracy and an indispensa­ble element of freedom, but because it is the guarantor of civil society itself. It protects the press, the academy, religion, political parties, and nonprofit associatio­ns like ours. In the era of Donald Trump, the importance of preserving these avenues for advancing justice and preserving democracy should be more evident than ever. —August 24, 2017

 ??  ?? White nationalis­ts marching on the University of Virginia campus, Charlottes­ville, August 2017
White nationalis­ts marching on the University of Virginia campus, Charlottes­ville, August 2017

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States