The New York Review of Books

Loving Assassins

- James Romm

The Tyrant-Slayers of Ancient Athens:

A Tale of Two Statues by Vincent Azoulay, translated from the French by Janet Lloyd, with a foreword by Paul Cartledge. Oxford University Press, 276 pp., $35.00

The Transforma­tion of Athens: Painted Pottery and the Creation of Classical Greece by Robin Osborne.

Princeton University Press,

285 pp., $49.95

In 514 BC the city of Athens, then under the control of the tyrant Hippias, witnessed a daring assassinat­ion, the first known political murder in European history. A pair of male lovers, the older named Aristogito­n and the younger Harmodius, plotted to kill Hippias at the Panathenai­c procession, a public ritual instituted by Peisistrat­us, Hippias’s father and the city’s previous ruler. But when Harmodius and Aristogito­n saw their target in conversati­on with someone who knew about their plot, they assumed they had been betrayed. As they fled, they encountere­d the tyrant’s brother, Hipparchus, and, being armed and mentally prepared, slew him instead of Hippias.

At first, the misdirecte­d blow might not have seemed consequent­ial. Hippias remained in power, the tyranny seemed secure, and the assassins, both killed in the aftermath of the crime, were rumored to have acted only out of personal motives—incensed, perhaps, that Hipparchus had coerced Harmodius into sexual relations and insulted his sister. But Hippias, disturbed by the near miss, began to take increasing­ly harsh measures to protect his family’s dynasty. In 510, when a Spartan interventi­on presented an opportunit­y to kick Hippias and his children out, the Athenians welcomed it, though they had seemed reasonably content with Peisistrat­id rule just a few years earlier. Harmodius and Aristogito­n had played only an indirect part in the ouster of Hippias, but they were nonetheles­s cast as freedom fighters and liberators. Within a few decades, their legend had grown to near-mythic proportion­s. Vase painters portrayed the murder of Hipparchus, the earliest known illustrati­ons of a historical event.1 A song celebratin­g their deed was de rigueur at late-fifth-century Athenian symposia, to judge by the writings of Aristophan­es and Plutarch. And the Athenians put on display a group of bronze statues that showed the pair striding into action, the first state-commission­ed images to depict real human beings rather than gods or figures of legend. Copies of these statues eventually spread throughout the ancient world. The drawn-sword poses of the two tyrannicid­es—especially that of Harmodius, with his right

1An earlier vase depicted the selfimmola­tion on a pyre of Croesus, king of Lydia, but this event was only quasi-historical, known to the Greeks through poetry and fable rather than direct experience. arm raised and cocked behind his left shoulder for a downward slash—became as recognizab­le and as suggestive of a free society as today’s raised-torch stance of the Statue of Liberty.2 Whatever they meant to achieve with their plot, Harmodius and Aristogito­n put Athens on a long course of political and social transforma­tion. A newcomer named Cleisthene­s filled the power vacuum left by Hippias and overhauled the constituti­on along populist lines, initiating a period of remarkable effloresce­nce. Athens gained an empire, built up its navy to dominating strength, and experiment­ed with ever-more radical means of transferri­ng power from the aristocrac­y to the dēmos, the masses. By the time the last witnesses to the killing of Hipparchus passed away, around 440 BC, Athens had become a far wealthier, vastly more democratic, and smarter city than in the late sixth century. It had arrived at what we now acknowledg­e to be its “golden age.” Through all these changes of Athenian political culture, as Vincent Azoulay explains in The Tyrant- Slayers of Ancient Athens, statues of Harmodius and Aristogito­n continued to beam to the Greek world their messages of liberation, fearless

2Due to a mistake in restoratio­n, corrected only in the 1950s, the Harmodius figure was long thought to have held his sword arm aloft and slightly forward, and is still seen in that pose in the bestpreser­ved Roman copy of the group, in Naples (see illustrati­on on this page). activism, and the redemptive power of erotic love.

Azoulay boldly attempts to resolve many difficult questions surroundin­g the tyrannicid­e statues, including where and when they were originally erected. A number of scholars trace them back to the rule of Cleisthene­s, but Azoulay disagrees, arguing that “it is hard to see why Cleisthene­s would have promoted a symbol that would tend to obscure his own role in the liberation of Athens.” He proposes instead that the statues were commission­ed after Athens repelled a Persian naval invasion in 490, accompanie­d by the aging Hippias hoping to return to power. Many in Athens shared his hope, and, after Persian forces were defeated at the plain of Marathon, a pro-Hippias faction within Athens apparently tried to signal them to mount a fresh assault. In Azoulay’s view, the victorious democrats subsequent­ly created the tyrannicid­e monument as a riposte to their foes and a declaratio­n that the rout of the Persians at Marathon had put a decisive end to Peisistrat­id rule.

But the Persians, now led by Xerxes, invaded a second time, in 480, and succeeded in capturing Athens; members of Hippias’s family, according to Herodotus, were once again in their train. The presence of these thirdgener­ation Peisistrat­ids explains, for Azoulay, the Persians’ decision to have the tyrannicid­e bronzes taken down and sent deep into their own territory. The disgrace of the tyrant’s family was thus symbolical­ly avenged. The Athenians, after regaining control of their city and driving out the invaders, escalated the quarrel by commission­ing new statues, in more costly marble, from the celebrated sculptors Critius and Nesiotes. The erection of this second monument can be precisely dated, on inscriptio­nal evidence, to 477 BC, and fixed to a particular location in the agora, the well-trafficked and highly public market square (a 1936 excavation there recovered a portion of a marble statue’s base, with Harmodius’s name legibly engraved on it). Ultimately the bronzes would be recovered and set up there as well, after the Persian empire fell to Alexander the Great a century and a half later.

Having linked the statues’ creation to a contest over the form of Athenian government, Azoulay proceeds to trace their fortunes and that of the legend of Harmodius and Aristogito­n from which they sprang. By the late fifth century, following two brief oligarchic overthrows of the Athenian democracy, opinions about the killing of Hipparchus had become split, as a passage from Thucydides informs us. Some in Athens claimed that Hipparchus, not his brother Hippias, had actually been the ruler at the time and that his murder had therefore been a true act of liberation, while others trivialize­d it, attributin­g it to purely private motives of erotic jealousy and offended honor. By this point, Athens had officially granted the high privilege of sitêsis—the right to free meals at state expense—to the living descendant­s of Harmodius,3 and an oath had been composed whereby all citizens swore to kill any future tyrant and to honor tyrant-slayers just as they honored Harmodius and Aristogito­n. Under pressure from its internal foes, supporters of Athenian democracy clung to the tyrannicid­es as talismans of inviolabil­ity and magnified the brothers’ deed into a direct attack on tyranny rather than a glancing blow.

The tyrannicid­e statues stand at the intersecti­on of many issues that interest Azoulay, some of which extend far beyond his expertise in classical Greek political history. He takes many interpreti­ve gambles and frequently admits that he is going out on a limb. Did satires and verbal attacks on the statue group reach a crescendo at the time of the first oligarchic revolution in Athens, in 411 BC? “In all probabilit­y they did, although there is no formal evidence to prove it,” Azoulay writes. Such speculatio­ns will dismay the more empiricall­y minded among the book’s readers, though others will find his brashness refreshing. In some cases, he certainly presses his evidence too hard, as when he cites painted vases that give “a wink or nudge” to the viewer by depicting various figures, including Amazons, in poses that, he claims, evoke those of the statues. It’s quite a stretch to imagine that, prompted only by the visual cues of swords held at certain

3Though portrayed as a beardless youth by sculptors, and as the junior partner of a male love-pair, Harmodius also evidently fathered at least one child.

angles, the users of these pots would link legendary barbarian women to historical Athenian males, or that the difference­s involved would evoke specific meanings rather than discourage all comparison.

One avenue that Azoulay starts down, and on which one wishes he traveled further, is the homoerotic dimension of the tyrannicid­es and their statues. He observes that, at least in the marble statue group, the pairing of a bearded man and a beardless, shorthaire­d youth would have evoked, for Athenian observers, a familiar pattern of intergener­ational male pair-bonding. The statues’ grafting of sexual desire onto the fight for political freedom thus anticipate­s a later dictum of Pericles (as quoted by Thucydides) that Athenians ought to have erotic passion for their democratic city. Azoulay notes this connection, but then veers off in an unexpected direction:

By exalting the union of the two assassin-lovers, the statuary group aimed to encourage spectators to identify with the protagonis­ts. The passer-by was encouraged to feel desire for the handsome Harmodius, so perfectly represente­d, and to put himself in the place of Aristogito­n . . . . Through its very arrangemen­t, this was a monument that had the power to draw a spectator into the scene, absorbing his very body and encouragin­g him to relive the liberating exploit of the two lovers.

Azoulay goes on to qualify this statement. In his conclusion, he argues that “one was forced to choose and identify oneself with either the victim or with the murderers” (my emphasis). But he fails to show why identifica­tion is the right model for the viewer’s response to this particular statue group, and he does not return to his initial, rather startling suggestion that the effect of this identifica­tion would be the evocation, in male viewers at least, of sexual desire.

The story of the tyrannicid­e statues becomes more episodic and patchy during the second half of Azoulay’s survey, in keeping with the dismal twists and turns of subsequent Athenian history. The Hellenisti­c dynasts who inherited the fragments of Alexander the Great’s empire came to control the political fortunes of the city in the late fourth century BC, and Roman armies arrived on the scene less than two centuries later. As Athens lost its autonomy and its form of government became a moot question, the message of the Harmodius and Aristogito­n statues grew increasing­ly confused. In the first century BC their outline, stamped on a coin, was deployed to show support for the Roman military strongman Lucius Cornelius Sulla, who may also have installed copies of the group on Rome’s Capitoline Hill. An image that had previously represente­d the rejection of state control was appropriat­ed, in Orwellian fashion, by a regime that sought to impose control through brute force. In his epilogue, Azoulay shows how adaptation­s of the tyrannicid­e statues in Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia resemble their exploitati­on by Sulla.

Azoulay sometimes struggles to connect disparate evidence into meaningful patterns and to fill gaps where evidence is lacking, but the overall design of his microhisto­ry is ingenious. By focusing on a single object originally found at the center of Athens, he conveys us meaningful­ly through seven centuries of political evolution: Harmodius and Aristogito­n become the fixed points around which all of Greek history revolves. By contrast, Robin Osborne, in The Transforma­tion of Athens, explores a wider range of images and artworks but limits himself to a far shorter period: roughly, the decades from 520 to 440 BC, the era of the so-called “Greek revolution” that produced the mature classical style in sculpture and painting as well as fullfledge­d Athenian democracy. Like Azoulay, Osborne is interested in the ways Athenian art and its reception changed in response to historical developmen­ts, but he is also playing for far bigger stakes—nothing less than (as his subtitle proclaims) “the creation of classical Greece.”

Though a historian by training (and by department­al affiliatio­n at Cambridge), Osborne rejects the traditiona­l historian’s reliance on textual evidence. As he explains in his preface:

The texts that we study were almost all written not simply at a definitive moment but for a definitive purpose; this makes it hard to recognize from texts when the way they present the world is instrument­al, a means to an end, and when the way they see the world reflects a view generally shared across the society.

That sentence will throw a glass of cold water in the face of many of Osborne’s fellow classicist­s (including myself), who might object that tragic dramas, at least, written as part of a prize competitio­n and performed before a large percentage of the population, have a fair claim on representi­ng views “generally shared across the society.” Osborne also has little love for the craft of art history, with its emphasis on influences, stylistic evolution, and technique. Though he takes works of art as his principal evidence, his objects of study are not the works themselves but rather the “ways of seeing the world” that produced them, and the ways they in turn trained their purchasers or spectators to see the world.

Having dealt in his previous study, The History Written on the Classical Greek Body, with evidence from both sculpture and vase painting, Osborne here restricts his inquiry to Athenian red-figure vases—the pots that became a staple of Athenian manufactur­e in the classical age, made by using a black glazed background to outline images against the natural red-brown of the clay. These were commoditie­s, created for sale in Athenian shops and also widely exported, especially to Etruscan cities in Italy. The fact that they were produced strictly for consumers is important to Osborne, since it means that no official program or patron’s directive determined their content:

Painters wanted to attract buyers’ attention, and might do that by being thought provoking, but they did not seek to teach .... The patterns of choice of scene to depict on pottery therefore have a strong chance of reproducin­g the way in which painters saw the world, unconstrai­ned by any need to persuade others or conform to others’ views.

This nondidacti­c character of painted pottery suits Osborne’s bottom-up approach to Greek history, although he also discusses state-sponsored—i.e., top-down—sculptures, including the tyrannicid­e groups of Critius and Nesiotes, in the final chapters. The fact that a large number of surviving Athenian pots have been recovered from Etruscan graves, rather than from Athens itself, does not trouble him; Etruria was “omnivorous” and merely absorbed what Athens sent its way, he argues. Some may find this an extreme position: art historians have in fact been deeply divided over how closely Athenian pots found in Etruria reflect Athenian tastes.

Although

Osborne also looks back briefly to earlier images in the blackfigur­e style, red-figure vases that came into fashion in Athens around 520 BC are the starting point of his study. The city was then just about to go through the events that concern Azoulay—the ouster of the tyrants and the democratic reforms of Cleisthene­s—but Osborne is not interested in them. He concentrat­es on vases that depict private, nonpolitic­al activities, on the assumption that these actions did not vary widely over time. Apart from mythologic­al scenes and portraits of the gods—which Osborne excludes from considerat­ion— the most common subjects of Athenian pots during the period in question were exercise in the gymnasium, soldiering, courting and lovemaking, drinking and carousing in the symposium, and religious sacrifices to the gods. He deals with these one by one in his core chapters, comparing a few select examples to trace how each type of scene was handled over the eight decades he studies.

Osborne’s decision to organize his study by subject, rather than by individual painters, pot shapes, or eras, is another way he distances himself from previous historians of Greek ceramics. In a polemical discussion of earlier work in the field, including that of the revered Sir John Beazley and Sir John Boardman, Osborne notes, “What all these explanatio­ns share with one another . . . is an exclusive concentrat­ion on form and style . . . . The subject represente­d is treated as just so much noise, to be eliminated so that the work of art can be seen more clearly.” Osborne is certainly interested in style, but equally concerned with choices about what gets represente­d, how it gets represente­d, and how these choices change over time.

Osborne notices a trend in the developmen­t of each of the five scene types he examines, and he even adds a sixth as a test case: depictions of satyrs, generated entirely from artists’ imaginatio­ns. Figures seen in vigorous, often contentiou­s activity in his earliest examples become more sedate and detached in later scenes:

Athletes no longer compete, they are no longer seen to run, jump, throw discus or javelin . . . . Soldiers no longer fight except in the stylized warfare with Persians or in mythologic­al combats . . . . Courtship ceases to be physically active. What we see is the athlete relaxing once the athletics is over, on his own or with others, the soldier within the domestic context, taking his helmet to go play his role in the army...individual­s deep in thought, concentrat­ing on what is to be done.

Osborne relies on various terms to describe this evolution, sometimes contrastin­g the two modes as “specific” versus “non-specific,” at other times as “theatrical” versus “absorbed” (the latter term is expanded at one point to “absorbed in their own worlds”). Turning to sculpture, Osborne cites the tyrannicid­e statues, which, because they represent “a particular action performed by particular men,” he takes as exemplars of the “theatrical­ity” of his archaic red-figure vases, as compared to the composed, contemplat­ive “absorption” of classical statuary.

What interests Osborne about these artistic trends is that they reflect “a transforma­tion in social expectatio­ns and values.” Drawing on a 1960 book by Arthur W. H. Adkins, Merit and Responsibi­lity: A Study in Greek Values, he describes this transforma­tion as a movement “from more individual­ist to more corporate” social attitudes, from an ethic of competitio­n to one of participat­ion. The mature Athenian democracy, as described in Pericles’ funeral oration, relied on a vision of civic community rather than rivalry between individual­s. Thus its artists increasing­ly emphasized “bodies that cannot be told apart, performing actions that do not open themselves up to judgments as to whether they are well or badly done.”

Experts will no doubt disagree with one or another of the premises of Osborne’s argument. The fact that much of his evidence comes from Etruscan gravesites, a sampling that some regard as skewed, is particular­ly worrisome. But Osborne’s gifts as an observer of ancient art are beyond dispute. His discussion­s of the vase scenes he has chosen to explore are filled with the kind of insight that make one inclined to accept any conclusion­s to which they might lead. His book offers a radically new approach to the Attic vases, one that might even achieve the two grand goals Osborne sets for it: not only to “rewrite the history of art” but also to “rewrite history.”

 ??  ?? Aristogito­n and Harmodius, Roman copies in marble after Greek bronze statues, circa fifth century
Aristogito­n and Harmodius, Roman copies in marble after Greek bronze statues, circa fifth century
 ??  ?? An Athenian red-figure vase depicting a woman doing her hair, circa 430
An Athenian red-figure vase depicting a woman doing her hair, circa 430

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States