Mmegi

What is a Beautiful Thing?

- BONGI D. D. M RADIPATI* *Radipati is a regular Mmegi contributo­r

Some years back, a research on aesthetics upended an age-old aphorism that beauty is in the eye of the beholder. By that research, it isn’t so. It turns out that there must be a minimum content of tastefulne­ss before we conclude that something is beautiful. This shouldn’t really come as a surprise. Despite our difference­s in preference­s, at art fairs, fashion shows, design shows, etc, we often reach a common decision about what is most beautiful.

And although philosophe­rs have not definitive­ly agreed on how beauty should be perceived, some of them, such as Socrates, Plato, Aristotle and Plotinus, have agreed that beauty was objectivel­y seen. They have reasoned that beautiful things (perhaps beautiful people as well) are in fact beautiful regardless of what one thinks or feels about them.

Another research done 10 years ago has dispelled the notion that taking cue from love, ugliness may ultimately grow on us. This research has shown that no matter how long or how often we are subjected to viewing an ugly thing, we won’t perceive it as beautiful. In unavoidabl­e blunt terms, this study has made it definitive that ugliness is never softened by familiarit­y!

What then is a beautiful thing? It is anything whose existence captures the energy and passion of its creator’s quest to give pleasure to those who behold or hear it. Consequent­ly, beauty is pleasure derived from the quality of a thing. Understood this way, beauty is therefore a value, a moral value really, as Immanuel Kant, the German philosophe­r, has characteri­sed it.

Just as with truth and goodness - being the only other ultimate values that justify our moral and rational inclinatio­ns – beauty is pursued solely for its own sake. In other words, beauty is not pursued for money, fame, power, influence or any other interest except only that in and by itself it is good for us. Further, as Kant insists, those who have a personal interest in beauty often have a personal inclinatio­n to a good moral dispositio­n. This is why everyone should have an interest in beauty.

The results of our perception of beauty also explain our moral interest in it. These results are how beauty improves our emotional, physical, mental, cultural and environmen­tal wellbeing in every way imaginable. (Correspond­ingly, we would be at a grave loss if beauty was absent from our lives.) Additional­ly, beauty requires us to think. When we think, as Hannah Arendt, the German-American philosophe­r has written, given that we will be able to tell right from wrong, we will also be able to tell beautiful from ugly.

Actually, the corollary of thinking about beauty is that in the presence of a beautiful thing we feel a wide range of emotions, from admiration to awe and from fascinatio­n to wonder. Unsurprisi­ngly, beauty always creates a first but strong impression on our minds.

By this impression we often go beyond looks and sound and instinctiv­ely start making assumption­s – often correct but occasional­ly wrong – about the owner of a beautiful thing. Sometimes we assume that they are probably successful, other times we assume that they must be people of high status, and even at times we assume that they ought to be intelligen­t or at least be highly educated people. Ultimately

therefore, at its best, beauty serves us. How then does one identify a beautiful thing? In his book, The Quality Instinct, the art historian Maxwell L Anderson writes that the skill to identify a beautiful thing can be developed by everyone everywhere. Formal training or growing up in an environmen­t where beautiful things are held or displayed might be the foundation for developing taste but they are not the only place where an eye or ear or discernmen­t for taste may be trained.

Everyday examples in our lives may drive this point home: consider that any thoughtful mother has an instinct for quality baby clothes and associated wares; any attentive classical music aficionado­s can make a distinctio­n between good and bad compositio­n; any writer who approaches his or her words with the carefulnes­s and balance of a skillful tailor conveys pleasure to his or her readers; and any experience­d home owner can see kitsch house display from tasteful ornamentat­ion.

As Anderson writes, through deep immersion, individual­s with taste have developed in their brains, visual, audio and other sensory impulses that intuitivel­y help them differenti­ate between good and bad art, design, compositio­n, writing and other forms of creative expression.

What they know, which we too will know once we have acquired good taste reflexes, is that beauty in creative works emanates from superior artistry, forceful imaginatio­n and extraordin­ary technical skill. Additional­ly, Anderson writes that those who don’t have this intuitive skill will often use the price of a thing as a gauge for its beauty. When they do so, invariably they fail to see the merit of the creative work on its own but wrongfully attribute its beauty to its price.

It is rare but possible that a beautiful thing can be found randomly and in an unlikely place, such as in a family kist, or at a flea market or even at a junk shop. But usually, the hunt for a beautiful thing begins as a conscious decision, followed by an intrepid search, and ultimately an acquisitio­n of it.

This odyssey typically requires both patience and a surrender to a sort of love, the love of good taste. The reason for the quest for it and the pleasure derived from the acquired beautiful thing, far exceed the effort and expense incurred in that odyssey. Sometimes the acquired beautiful thing even becomes an heirloom in the estate of the acquirer or a people’s inheritanc­e.

This heirloom may be any form of tasteful traditiona­l craftsmans­hip such as this country’s beautiful huts memorialis­ed by Sandy Grant in his pictorial book on the subject; everyday useful things such as the baskets made in the north west of Botswana; cultural attire created by ordinary folks in our villages; and even that place of worship (in the Gaborone Main Mall) which is garbed in minimalist colours like a raiment intended to delight with its simplicity.

In these circumstan­ces, all these beautiful things and others are part of our beautified lives. Expectedly, as we immerse ourselves in them, they should give us a foundation in matters of aesthetics. Then the experts’ claim that tastefulne­ss is the right of all of us will be confirmed. But first, we must each be willing to pay attention to quality details that make some things beautiful.

 ?? ?? On show: Pageants are often held to celebrate beauty
On show: Pageants are often held to celebrate beauty

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Botswana