The Guardian (Charlottetown)

What does Quebec euthanasia ruling say about us as Canadians?

- EWAN GOLIGHER GUEST OPINION Dr. Ewan Goligher is an assistant professor of medicine at the University of Toronto.

On Sept. 11, a Quebec judge overturned the law restrictin­g euthanasia to patients in whom natural death was reasonably foreseeabl­e. The federal government has indicated that they will not appeal the decision and are prepared to modify the law accordingl­y. These developmen­ts require sober considerat­ion, for they speak volumes about the inexorable logic of euthanasia and about our attitudes towards those with disabiliti­es. The Quebec ruling must be overturned to prevent further cascading demands on assisted dying legislatio­n and to safeguard our most vulnerable citizens.

Euthanasia is offered as a means of escaping pointless and irremediab­le suffering. Yet we need not be dying in order to experience suffering that seems pointless and hopeless to us. Therefore, restrictin­g euthanasia to those in whom natural death is reasonably foreseeabl­e violates the intrinsic logic of euthanasia. If life is sufficient­ly hard, and suffering sufficient­ly grievous, we might come to think that we are better off dead long before natural death becomes reasonably foreseeabl­e. Such is the bleak logic of euthanasia. Following this logic, is it possible to put any limits on euthanasia at all?

Just what kinds of suffering should be eligible for euthanasia? Surely psychologi­cal and existentia­l suffering are just as (if not more) unbearable than physical pain. Therefore, patients with protracted severe depression and mental illness should also be eligible, as some argue.

What if I merely anticipate grievous suffering and this makes life pointless to me? What if my condition might get better but I don’t want to wait and endure to find out? How disabled do I need to be for my suffering to qualify for euthanasia? And who gets to answer these questions?

Any attempt to impose answers to these questions upon individual patients violates the commitment to personal autonomy and control that underpins the logic of euthanasia — as Dying with Dignity Canada states: “My life, my choice.” Followed to its logical conclusion, euthanasia is really for anyone at any time under any circumstan­ces, provided they want it. Those who accept this logic will not be satisfied until all restrictio­ns are removed. Lurking behind this logic are assumption­s about autonomy and vulnerabil­ity.

A decision expresses your autonomy insofar as you “own” the decision: it reflects your wishes and values and is not imposed upon you in any way. This notion of autonomy assumes that all of us can rise above the forces acting upon us from without, and here we detect a grave possibilit­y of error. Overt efforts at coercion may be easily detected and resisted, but the subtle influences of societal valuation are harder to appreciate and far more irresistib­le.

How then might general social acceptance and approval for euthanasia of persons with disabiliti­es influence their sense of personal value? What does social approval for this act say about us and our values and attitudes toward those with disabiliti­es? Do we view those with disabiliti­es as merely expendable, free to have their lives ended if they so choose without protest on our part? By comparison, would we protest if a healthy young woman sought to end her life because of persistent bullying on social media?

A society that prizes and prioritize­s the most vulnerable amongst us is a safe place for all of us to flourish. Such a society makes every effort to communicat­e that each of us matters and prohibits anything that diminishes our individual value. The death of those with disabiliti­es is as profound a loss for all of us as much as is the death of those without disabiliti­es.

The Quebec Court’s decision of Sept. 11, 2019 must be overturned. Canadians must demand it.

 ?? 123RF.COM PHOTO ??
123RF.COM PHOTO

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Canada