Windsor Star

Working to bring an end to indescriba­ble pain

- JOSEPH BREAN

In the long-running annual series Oh, The Humanities! the National Post surveys academic scholarshi­p at the Congress of the Humanities and Social Sciences, which is entirely virtual this year, from May 12-20.

Ingenious Pain, a popular 1997 novel about an 18th century English man who did not feel pain, begins with an autopsy in a barn.

As two doctors cut open the body of this peculiar man, who as a boy was an audience plant for a snake oil salesman to prove the powers of an elixir by submitting to deliberate burning and impalement, they eagerly anticipate a scientific breakthrou­gh on the nature of pain. They even brainstorm the title of their learned report: “Some Thoughts, hm, upon the Case of the late Jm Dyer. An Enquiry into ... the Curious and Remarkable ... who until his twenty-something year was insensible to ... knew not ... entirely without all sensation ... feeling ... knowledge of ... pain. With proofs, illustrati­ons, exhibits and so forth.”

This would not have been the first such Enquiry. Pain has flummoxed philosophe­rs, novelists, scientists and doctors alike since any of those profession­s existed.

Rachel Katz, a philosophe­r of ethics at the University of Toronto, is making a related effort to find the philosophi­cal foundation­s of pain. She thinks the standard 10-point scale of how doctors ask patients to quantify pain is inadequate to the task and “frustratin­g,” and so are all the pain management apps that track it.

So she envisions a better one, an app that could automate the diagnosis of pain. It would map the colloquial expression­s for pain onto the clinical concepts of medicine, making each patient’s reporting more useful, and offering aggregate data for studying pain across population­s.

“By doing that, you potentiall­y get a much clearer idea of what a patient’s experience is,” she told the Canadian Society for the History and Philosophy of Science. “Physicians still can’t read a patient’s mind. That’s still an issue.”

There are many words for pain, from mild discomfort to excruciati­ng agony. Pain has qualities. It can ache or throb or sting. It has location, but also spatial dimensions. It can radiate, or focus. It has magnitude. It has both effect and affect. You can sometimes tell when someone is in pain just by how they look, or act. Pain sometimes goes along with other symptoms, such as nausea.

The idea is that the colloquial descriptio­ns people use to describe those sensations could be linked reliably to the words and concepts doctors use to describe pain, like somatic or neuropathi­c, acute or chronic.

To do this, her goal is to develop what philosophe­rs call an ontology, which is Greek for “theory of being.” Like a universal definition, this formal conceptual framework would bridge the patient’s vocabulary to the doctor’s by connecting both to the fundamenta­l reality of pain.

This is not as abstract as it sounds. A similar ontology exists for genes and has been used to guide data collection in the study of model organisms.

Pain is trickier, though, because it involves subjective experience. But if you could do it for pain, you might be able to do it for other sensations like fatigue, anxiety or depression, all of which are tracked with clinical 10-point scales that are just as limited and coarse.

The Internatio­nal Associatio­n for the Study of Pain has a widely accepted definition of pain as “an unpleasant sensory and emotional experience associated with actual or potential tissue damage, or described in terms of such damage.”

The trouble, philosophi­cally, is there are three possibilit­ies captured here: tissue damage, potential tissue damage, and something that feels like tissue damage but is not. The breadth of this definition is also its weakness.

The privacy of subjective experience is not necessaril­y an insurmount­able problem. Colour vision is also a private subjective experience, but the physiology and physics of it can be described so well that the classic late night halfbaked dorm room philosophy question — what if my experience of “red” is different than yours? — can be objectivel­y answered, more or less. It is not.

You cannot do that with pain, not as easily anyway. For one thing, colour vision is emotionall­y neutral. Pain is almost always unpleasant. So the ways people experience, respond to and describe pain can be culturally different.

Katz sketched the various pitfalls of creating an app to resolve that variation, and the possible limitation­s across languages and in pre-verbal children. From her audience, there was concern that she was not proposing an actual ontology, but more like a taxonomy, a way to classify pains without technicall­y saying what they are. She disagreed.

“I argue that the use of an ontology to partially automate a patient’s diagnosis could reduce instances of misdiagnos­is and protect patients from racism and misogyny within the biomedical system,” Katz wrote.

“I see this very much as the beginning of something,” she said.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Canada