The New Zealand Herald

Weapon of paranoid elite must go

Term ‘conspiracy theory’ a tool to protect powerful

- David Coady David Coady is a senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Tasmania.

Tolabelabe­liefasa conspiracy theory is to imply it’s false.

Before 2012, if you had voiced suspicions that the Australian Government had been anything but open and honourable in dealing with East Timor — its newly independen­t but impoverish­ed neighbour — you would likely have been dismissed as a conspiracy theorist.

But it was then revealed Australian Secret Intelligen­ce Service agents had bugged East Timor’s Cabinet office during treaty negotiatio­ns over oil and gas fields.

Yesterday’s conspiracy theories often become today’s immutable facts. In the mid-1990s, journalist Gary Webb’s claims that CIA officials conspired with drug dealers bringing crack cocaine into the United States were dismissed by many as a prime example of a conspiracy theory. But the claims were true.

It’s reasonable to suppose many views now dismissed as conspiracy theories will one day be recognised as having been true all along.

Indeed, the net effect of terms such as “conspiracy theory” is to silence people who are the victims of conspiracy, or who (rightly or wrongly) suspect conspiraci­es may be occurring. These terms serve to herd respectabl­e opinion in ways that suit the interests of the powerful.

Ever since the philosophe­r Sir Karl Popper popularise­d the expression in the 1950s, conspiracy theories have had a bad reputation.

To label a belief as a conspiracy theory is to imply it’s false. More than that, it implies people who accept that belief, or want to investigat­e whether it’s true, are irrational.

On the face of it, this is hard to understand. After all, people do conspire. Conspiracy is a common form of human behaviour across all cultures throughout recorded time, and it has always been particular­ly widespread in politics.

Given people conspire, there can’t be anything wrong with believing they conspire. Hence there can’t be anything wrong with believing conspiracy theories or being a conspiracy theorist.

Thinking of conspiracy theories as paradigmat­ically false and irrational is like thinking of phrenology as a paradigm of scientific theory.

Conspiracy theories, like scientific theories, and virtually any other type of theory, are sometimes true, sometimes false, sometimes held on rational grounds, sometimes not.

It’s a striking feature of much of the literature on conspiracy theories, like much of the literature on terrorism, that authors assume they are referring to the same phenomenon, while a glance at their definition­s (when they bother to offer them) reveals they are not.

But seeking a fixed definition of the term “conspiracy theory” may be an idle goal, since the real problem with the term is, although it lacks a fixed meaning, it serves a fixed function.

A new Inquisitio­n?

It’s a function similar to that served by the term “heresy” in medieval Europe. In both cases these are terms of propaganda, used to stigmatise and marginalis­e people who have beliefs that conflict with officially sanctioned or orthodox beliefs of the time.

If, as I believe, the treatment of those labelled as “conspiracy theorists” in our culture is analogous to the treatment of those labelled as “heretics” in medieval Europe, then the role of psychologi­sts and social scientists in this treatment is analogous to that of the Inquisitio­n.

Outside the psychology and social science literature some authors will sometimes offer some, usually heavily qualified, defence of conspiracy theories (in some sense of the term).

But among psychologi­sts and social scientists the assumption that they are false, the product of an irrational (or nonrationa­l) process, and positively harmful is virtually universal.

Whenever we use the terms “conspiracy theory”, “conspiraci­sm” or “conspiraci­st ideation”, we’re implying, even if we don’t mean to, there is something wrong with believing, wanting to investigat­e, or giving any credence at all to the possibilit­y people are engaged in secretive or deceptive behaviour.

One bad effect of these terms is they add to a political environmen­t in which it’s easier for conspiracy to thrive at the expense of openness. Another bad effect is their use is an injustice to the people who are characteri­sed as conspiracy theorists.

Following the philosophe­r Miranda Fricker, we may call this a form of “testimonia­l injustice”.

When someone asserts that a conspiracy has occurred (especially when it is a conspiracy by powerful people or institutio­ns) that person’s word is automatica­lly given less credence than it should because of an irrational prejudice associated with the pejorative connotatio­ns of these terms.

I hope and believe that in the future these terms will be widely recognised for what they are: the products of an irrational and authoritar­ian outlook. Prior to Popper, we got along perfectly well without these terms. I’m sure we can learn to do so again.

 ??  ?? The 2014 film Kill The Messenger,starring Jeremy Renner as US journalist Gary Webb, whose claims the CIA was conspiring with drug trafficker­s were dismissed as conspiracy theory but proved to be true.
The 2014 film Kill The Messenger,starring Jeremy Renner as US journalist Gary Webb, whose claims the CIA was conspiring with drug trafficker­s were dismissed as conspiracy theory but proved to be true.
 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from New Zealand