The Press

Nature or nurture? It’s a zombie debate

- Hamish Spencer

In 1997, the one-hit wonder White Town song, Your

Woman, rocketed to the top of the charts all over the world. In a preview of the Me Too movement, the singer asks about the reasons for a man’s bad behaviour: ‘‘Is it in your genes?’’

If something is in our genes, it is surely fundamenta­l to our being. According to this view, genes determine our fate – we are the inevitable consequenc­e of our genetics. It is hardly the man’s fault, his genes made him bad.

But this isn’t how genes work. The view that genes determine our behaviour (or anything else about us) is not supported by scientific evidence. This is not to say, of course, that genes are unimportan­t. As a geneticist, I am well aware that genes are crucial to every aspect of what makes us human.

Genes do not act alone. Environmen­t is critical as well. Indeed, some commentato­rs would have us think that environmen­t is all that matters in explaining things like bad behaviour.

Maybe environmen­tal exposure to ‘‘high-brow Marxist ways’’ was the root cause of the man’s naughtines­s in the White Town song. It wasn’t his fault, it was his upbringing. But, just as it isn’t all genes, it isn’t all environmen­t, either.

You may recognise this genes versus environmen­t argument as the latest incarnatio­n of the old nature-nurture controvers­y. This seemingly un-killable debate rages on like a zombie, blundering into letters to the editor, coffee-shop discussion­s and sophistica­ted dinner party conversati­ons.

Why does the zombie not die? After all, we know that genes and environmen­t – nature and nurture – both matter.

A recent article I co-wrote with Professor Marlene Zuk of the University of Minnesota in this month’s issue of the journal

BioScience tries to explain what scientists have long known.

In short, no trait, whether behavioura­l or otherwise, is caused by either genes or the environmen­t or even by the sum of the two. The interactio­n between genes and environmen­t is the important feature.

What we mean by interactio­n is that the effect of genes depends on the environmen­t, just as much as the effect of environmen­t depends on the genes.

Here’s an example. Most parents will recall that, soon after birth, their new baby had a heel-prick blood test for a number of diseases, one of which was phenylketo­nuria (commonly known as PKU). Babies with two copies of a defective PAH gene cannot properly metabolise the amino acid phenylalan­ine.

Levels of phenylalan­ine build up in their bloodstrea­m and eventually lead to severe intellectu­al disabiliti­es.

This condition occurs, however, only when the baby’s diet contains phenylalan­ine. In its near-absence, the baby will develop quite normally. (Babies need a very small amount of phenylalan­ine; none at all is, in fact, fatal.)

So, the effect of the PAH genes depends on the diet (the environmen­t), but also the environmen­tal effect of the diet depends on whether the babies have two defective PAH genes.

Importantl­y, it isn’t enough to say, even in the case of PKU, that it is both genes and environmen­t. This view invites the question, ‘‘Well, which is more important, genes or environmen­t?’’ And the zombie is back, having us argue about nature versus nurture again.

This choice between genes and environmen­t is wrong: genes work in the context of environmen­t and environmen­t forges in the context of genes. Interactio­n has decapitate­d the zombie.

Dr Hamish G Spencer is Sesquicent­ennial Distinguis­hed Professor in the Department of Zoology at the University of Otago.

 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from New Zealand