Manila Bulletin

Thoughts from the past on cyberlibel

- By JUSTICE ART D. BRION (RET.) artbrion91­6.legalfront.mb@ gmail.com

THE

recent case of Maria Ressa once more highlighte­d the cybercrime law which had attracted public attention in 2014 when oppositors constituti­onally challenged its cyberlibel provision, among others. I was one of those who supported the challenge to the cyberlibel provision, but the court ruled against our opposition.

Without any reference to the pending Maria Ressa case (that, despite claims aired in advance of the formal proceeding­s, may or may not involve free speech issues), I relive my old thoughts on this precious freedom.

Traditiona­l libel is the public and malicious imputation of a crime, vice, or defect, real or imaginary, tending to dishononor or discredit a natural or juridical person or to blacken the memory of one who is dead. Cyberlibel (or Internet libel) carries the same definition except that the communicat­ion or publicatio­n of the imputation is through the Internet. It also carries a penalty heavier than the penalty for traditiona­l libel.

In upholding the provision’s validity, the court found that Congress passed the law in the exercise of its power to define and penalize crimes. The court reasoned out that substantia­l distinctio­ns exist between cyberlibel and traditiona­l libel to justify the increased penalty for cyberlibel.

My dissent was not based on the unconstitu­tionality of libel per se. Jurisprude­nce has long settled that libel is not protected speech and Congress, may validly prohibit its utterance.

I dissented because I found the increase in penalty for Internet libel to be constituti­onally objectiona­ble. In my view, the cyberlibel provision, insofar as it qualified the crime of libel, violated our cherished freedom of speech because it unreasonab­ly increased the prohibitiv­e effect of libel law on online speech.

First, I did not see any significan­t distinctio­n in law between libelous speech made through the Internet and speech uttered in the real, physical world, to warrant the increased penalty.

Second, the increased penalty for Internet libel effectivel­y leads to self-censorship in the Internet and unreasonab­ly limits an otherwise robust medium for debate and discussion of public issues. Online discussion­s may contain both libelous and non-libelous matters; the deterrent effect of the harsher penalty can prevent even constituti­onally protected non-libelous speech from being uttered.

The court pinned its justificat­ion on the capabiliti­es of Internet communicat­ions: its speed, worldwide reach, and the relative anonymity it affords. It noted that cybercrime­s, including cyberlibel, are more perverse than traditiona­l crimes because of the anonymity and undeserved relative protection from prosecutio­n it affords to perpetrato­rs.

I did not contest the claim that Internet communicat­ions can indeed contribute to a libelous statement’s harmful effect on another. A libelous article, once published and openly shared in the Internet, could reach millions in a short period of time, and inflict more injury to reputation­s.

I considered though that the element of publicatio­n under both traditiona­l libel and cyberlibel are the same. For prosecutio­n purposes, a defamatory statement is considered published when it is transmitte­d to a third person other than the speaker or the person defamed.

Thus, the sender of a libelous e-mail might have intended to communicat­e with only one specific recipient who in fact solely viewed the email, yet, the sender would be penalized with a harsher penalty. Similarly, a person, who in an online chat with another, privately uttered a libelous statement about a third person, would also be similarly penalized. In both instances, the law imposes a higher penalty due solely to the Internet’s potential to reach millions.

The same reasoning applies to the anonymity afforded by Internet communicat­ions: a libelous author concealing his identity would be similarly penalized as a person identifyin­g himself, simply because both of them used the Internet as the medium for their libelous statements.

I considered further that the element of publicatio­n of traditiona­l libel (on which cyberlibel is based) does not consider the number of the recipients to be material. Libelous speech is penalized whether it reaches a single person by mail, or many persons through television or through a nationwide newspaper article. In all these, the defamatory imputation­s are punishable with the same penalty, a range within prision correccion­al or a fine, or both.

If the number of audience is not material under the original concept of libel, I do not see why cyberlibel, simply because of the use of the Internet, should merit a harsher manner.

I reasoned out, too, that the court should not rule on the basis of unusual and extreme situations and use these to justify the increased penalty for cyberlibel. If the court must err, it must err on the side of protecting freedom of speech, a fundamenta­l right very high in the hierarchy of our constituti­onal freedoms.

I noted finally that despite the passage of the Cybercrime Law, bills punishing cyber-bullying and electronic violence had been filed in Congress. Cyber-bullying is the act of using social media to “harm or harass other people in a deliberate, repeated, and hostile manner.” Electronic Violence, on the other hand, is any act involving the exploitati­on of data that “can cause or is likely to cause mental, emotional, and psychologi­cal distress or suffering to the victim.”

These bills, in my view, revealed the underlying intent not to penalize extreme situations similar to what the court’s interpreta­tion would allow. In cyberlibel, in particular, the law only recognized and clarified that the crime of libel may be committed through computer communicat­ions.

As then Chief Justice Sereno likewise pointed out, the cyberlibel provision did not only consider Internet use to be a qualifying aggravatin­g circumstan­ce that cannot be offset by mitigating circumstan­ces; it also: increased the accessory penalties for libel; disqualifi­ed the offender from availing of the privilege of probation; and increased the prescripti­ve periods for libel and for its penalty.

These effects, taken together, unduly burdened freedom of speech as they extended beyond what was necessary to prevent the commission of cyberlibel: they fostered self-censorship in the Internet and effectivel­y curtailed otherwise protected online speech.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from Philippines