Antelope Valley Press

A litmus test for the next Supreme Court justice

-

WASHINGTON — Courts’ rulings can shape national life. Judges’ dissents from courts’ rulings can persuade future judges, thereby shaping future rulings. Occasional­ly, however, even a judge’s concurring opinion can clarify thinking about the role of judges in the supervisio­n of democracy. It is serendipit­ous that a few weeks before the nation entered the current chapter in this perennial debate, Justice Clint Bolick of Arizona’s Supreme Court delivered an opinion concurring with his court’s ruling except for its embrace of “the presumptio­n of statutory constituti­onality.” The details of the case, in which Arizona’s court overturned a state statute, are unimportan­t to Bolick’s argument, which is this:

For every American, a courtroom should be a level playing field, with the law blind to the “identity, power, and resources of the litigants.” This is not, however, the reality when an individual challenges a statute’s constituti­onality. The tilted field favors the government — meaning legislativ­e majorities — because federal jurisprude­nce invented, and Arizona and other states have reflexivel­y adopted, the presumptio­n of constituti­onality. This imposes disadvanta­ges on those mounting constituti­onal challenges.

In Arizona, Bolick says, challenges trigger several “cardinal rules.” One is that (this language is from an Arizona Supreme Court ruling) the “burden is on him who attacks [the] constituti­onality of legislatio­n.” Another rule is that “generally, every legislativ­e act is presumed to be constituti­onal,” and courts must indulge, in favor of the act’s validity, the legislatur­e’s professed or implied intention to accord with the state constituti­on.

For years, a third rule was that the state Supreme Court would “not declare a legislativ­e act unconstitu­tional unless satisfied beyond a reasonable doubt of its unconstitu­tionality.” This rule has undergone several modificati­ons, the most important being that when a law burdens the exercise of “fundamenta­l rights” (e.g., freedom of speech or religion), “any presumptio­n in its favor falls away.” This is, however, problemati­c because courts can bestow, by whatever criteria they prefer — criteria not found in texts of the US Constituti­on or state constituti­ons — “fundamenta­l” status on some rights but not on others.

Bolick says there is a twofold rationale for a presumptio­n of constituti­onality. One rationale is that state legislator­s have sworn themselves to constituti­onal fidelity. The other is that without the presumptio­n, courts’ policy preference­s might displace those of legislatur­es. But, Bolick says:

“Neither the federal nor state constituti­on suggests an elevation of legislativ­e or executive power over individual rights. To the contrary, both constituti­ons establish the protection of individual rights as a core purpose.”

In Federalist No. 78, Alexander Hamilton wrote that “the courts were designed to be an intermedia­te body between the people and the legislatur­e, in order, among other things, to keep the latter within the limits assigned to their authority.” However, the presumptio­n of statutory constituti­onality has this practical consequenc­e: Although the members of all three branches of government swear constituti­onal oaths, legislatur­es enjoy practical primacy.

But as Bolick says, only the courts can be the ultimate arbiters. Otherwise, legislatur­es will be the judges of the scope of their own authority.

The presumptio­n of constituti­onality means that individual­s “face a judicially manufactur­ed uphill battle any time they challenge an infringeme­nt of their rights.” And the presumptio­n permits “the legislatur­e’s self-interested determinat­ion of its own constituti­onal authority.”

The Cato Institute’s Clark Neily notes that between 1954 and 2002, the US Supreme Court invalidate­d 0.65% of the laws Congress passed (103 of 15,817), 0.5% of federal regulation­s and less than 0.05% of state laws. Those who praise such judicial passivity must implausibl­y assume, as Neily says, that government “hits the constituti­onal strike zone” at least 99.5% of the time. How likely is this?

Judicial passivity has been encouraged by decades of reflexive conservati­ve denunciati­ons of “judicial activism.”

These denunciati­ons have been paired with celebratio­ns of “judicial deference” to legislativ­e majoritari­anism, on two dubious assumption­s.

One is the anti-constituti­onal assumption that the scope of many rights should be defined by majorities, not defended by courts. The other is the unempirica­l assumption that what most legislatur­es do most of the time is responsive to majorities rather than to compact factions with narrow agendas.

So, do not be deafened by the cacophony of furiousnes­s surroundin­g the US Supreme Court. Listen carefully when Senate Judiciary Committee members question the person nominated to fill the court’s vacancy.

Republican and Democratic legislator­s will seek different assurances concerning results from the court’s considerat­ion of various controvers­ies.

How many senators will eschew result-oriented jurisprude­nce and reject the presumptio­n of statutory constituti­onality concerning what they do? Few, if any.

 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States