Arkansas Democrat-Gazette

Getting rights wrong

- Freelance columnist Bradley R. Gitz, who lives and teaches in Batesville, received his Ph.D. in political science from the University of Illinois.

The concept of “rights” once had a clear meaning; under the influence of progressiv­e thought that meaning has been purposely obscured.

For the American founders and the classical liberals who influenced them (and today’s conservati­ves and libertaria­ns, heirs to that classical liberal tradition), human beings were endowed with “inalienabl­e rights” by virtue of their humanity and prior to the establishm­ent of government.

Within this context, government is brought into being to secure such rights and thereby move us from Thomas Hobbes’ partly metaphoric­al “state of nature” (“nasty, brutish and short”) to a world where our lives and property are protected from the transgress­ions of our neighbors.

The creation of government therefore solves the first theoretica­l challenge of politics through a “social contract” in which we agree to live according to the laws of the community in return for the security for ourselves and our rights that that community provides.

Alas, the solution to the second great problem—how to safeguard our rights against the same government we brought into being to protect them—has historical­ly proven more daunting. As the founders were well aware, tyranny in various forms had been the common, dismal human experience, whether the tyrants in question were called kings, czars, emirs, sultans or emperors.

Thus, what was created at Philadelph­ia in 1787 would represent the most successful effort in history to strike a balance between a system of government that was sufficient­ly powerful to protect rights but not so powerful as to threaten them. “A nation of laws, not men” would be based upon a system of checks and balances to the benefit of freedom (defined as the exercise of rights).

Central to all this was the understand­ing that the state exists to protect rights, not grant them. And that government must be kept limited and constraine­d in various ways lest it become a threat to liberty (which is also why progressiv­es who champion a powerful, activist government are fundamenta­lly illiberal).

The essential point is that the exercise of liberal rights, including those codified in the first 10 amendments to our Constituti­on (speech, press, assembly, religion, etc.), imposes no costs on others and requires no subsidy by the state; rather, it is crucial that the state infringe upon them only with great justificat­ion and in accord with due process.

Contained within this conception of rights was also a necessary but often misunderst­ood right to “property.”

Lest we forget, the original Jeffersoni­an formulatio­n was not “life, liberty, and happiness,” but, following the most important influence on the founders, John Locke, “life, liberty, and property.” And that such a conception of a right to “property” meant much more than simply material goods and satisfacti­ons—to the contrary, it represente­d the cumulative consequenc­es of the exercise of our other rights; more precisely, the opportunit­ies that a free society allowed for individual­s to utilize their talents, ambitions and judgment in securing happiness.

Property, then, was a composite expression of all other rights because it was the result of an individual’s exercise of them over the course of a lifetime. It included not just wealth but also the personal autonomy of a free person.

All of which directs our attention to the crucial distinctio­n between traditiona­l liberal rights and some of the more dubious ones championed by contempora­ry leftists masqueradi­ng as liberals.

A right to health care, housing, or education is morally compelling at first glance and always electorall­y enticing—who, after all, doesn’t want everyone to have such things, as well as laptop computers, a well-paid job, nice cars and paid vacations? But the catch is that such “positive” rights can come only by government provision. And that provision can, in turn, come only from government if government uses coercion to take the means of provision from others, thereby violating their rights (property) in the process.

Traditiona­l rights like speech, religion and assembly are exercised with no infringeme­nt upon and independen­t of the rights of others; the positive rights asserted by socialists and their progressiv­e cousins necessaril­y involve a zero-sum, government-managed process of rights redistribu­tion.

When a right to housing is asserted, for instance, it can only be provided by the state if it takes housing, or at least the income (property) to purchase it, from other citizens; indeed, the idea that rights can be redistribu­ted and dependent upon state subsidy is cancerous to the very concept of rights.

Thus, when politician­s promise various benefits under the misleading banner of rights (the latest being a “living wage” and free college), they are, by definition, violating the rights of those who will be forced to pay for the promised benefits, as well as underminin­g our understand­ing of the nature and sources of rights.

Put differentl­y, no proper understand­ing of rights would grant someone a right to the fruits of someone else’s labor.

Speech is free. So, too, is the right to worship as one pleases. But nothing government provides is. Because there is no free lunch, there can’t be a right to one, either.

Indeed, the monstrous state necessary to guarantee that all receive the necessitie­s of life “according to need” must always destroy genuine rights and individual liberty.

 ??  ??
 ?? Bradley R. Gitz ??
Bradley R. Gitz
 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States