Arkansas Democrat-Gazette

Our illiberal liberals

- Bradley R. Gitz Freelance columnist Bradley R. Gitz, who lives and teaches in Batesville, received his Ph.D. in political science from the University of Illinois.

One of the more frustratin­g aspects of American politics is our misuse of ideologica­l labels, including the tendency to reflexivel­y refer to everyone on the political left as “liberals” even when they hold views bearing little resemblanc­e to liberalism, properly defined.

The idea that everything on the left is “liberal” is inherently nonsensica­l, suggesting that among the most liberal societies on earth were Stalin’s Soviet Union and Chairman Mao’s China.

In reality, the “classical liberal” tradition developed out of the ideas of David Hume, Adam Smith, John Locke and the broader European (more precisely, Scottish) Enlightenm­ent. It decisively influenced the American founding and guided the spread of freedom and self-government to all points of the globe, defeating illiberal challenger­s like monarchy, fascism and various strains of communism along the way.

The movement away from this form of liberalism in the first nation founded explicitly upon liberal principles has been a gradual one, but has now produced what is in many ways the antithesis of the original thing.

The difference­s can be seen along four key dimensions:

In views of freedom and equality. The quintessen­tial classical liberals, the American founders, considered “liberty” to be the highest political value, defined as the right of people to live as they pleased so long as they respected the right of others to do the same.

Contempora­ry liberals place much lower emphasis upon such a form of freedom, preferring to subordinat­e it to newer, more radical conception­s of equality. Although classical liberals insisted upon equality before the law and in terms of rights, today’s liberals increasing­ly embrace equality of outcome or result drawn from socialist rather than liberal thought.

In many ways, the more free the society the less “equal” it becomes, at least in terms of the forms of equality most valued by the left.

The role of government/the state. Whereas classical liberalism was distinguis­hed by efforts to diffuse political authority and thereby limit the power of the state (in order to prevent the kind of tyranny that threatened liberty), contempora­ry liberals wish to centralize political power in order to pursue increasing­ly egalitaria­n policies.

The “natural inequaliti­es” which the founders saw as the inevitable consequenc­e of the exercise of freedom are for contempora­ry leftists to be eradicated by abridging freedom, even if doing so removes the constraint­s upon state power historical­ly undergirdi­ng liberalism.

In attitudes toward private property and capitalism. Classical liberals felt that the protection of private property, the essence of what Karl Marx called “capitalism,” was crucial to liberty. In James Madison’s formulatio­n, the protection of such property, which flowed from the inevitable diversity of human ambitions and “faculties,” was the “first object of government.”

For the contempora­ry left, such property rights present an obstacle to the desired redistribu­tion of wealth by an all-powerful state. The pursuit of equality of result/outcome thus requires the replacemen­t of market economic arrangemen­ts with collectivi­st and statist approaches.

The basis of rights. For classical liberals, “unalienabl­e” rights inhered in us by virtue of our shared humanity, not as members of groups based on race, ethnicity, or gender. The very notion of “group rights” was thought to be an illiberal derivative of pre-liberal feudalism with its rigid class hierarchie­s.

Ironically, given the historical role that liberalism played in replacing group with individual rights, contempora­ry liberals now assign rights and opportunit­ies for political participat­ion purely in terms of such “group” identity and membership.

For the “intersecti­onality/identity politics” left, rights are granted or (withheld) not to individual­s but according to the degree to which they can demonstrat­e membership in the right racial, ethnic, or gender groups along precisely the kinds of rigid hierarchie­s that once characteri­zed medieval life; with “right” defined by their capacity to claim victim status at the hands of the “patriarchy” or “whiteness.”

Race, ethnicity and gender determine political status because everything else in life is assumed to be determined by race, ethnicity and gender.

These inversions of classical liberalism help us to explain much about the contempora­ry left, including its rejection of due process and presumptio­ns of innocence (the Kavanaugh hearings), the discarding of constituti­onalism (“living constituti­on” jurisprude­nce, which is actually little more than a grant to impose leftist values without formal constituti­onal amendment), and the embrace of the “administra­tive state” (with roots in the progressiv­e vision of impartial “experts” managing an increasing­ly complex society, and which endorses centralize­d power without accountabi­lity).

Finally, and perhaps most tellingly, leftists have now abandoned the core liberal principle of freedom of speech and expression enshrined in the First Amendment, even to the point of demonizing those who support it as defenders of “hate.”

But enforcing speech codes, silencing dissent by “de-platformin­g” speakers, and imposing rigid forms of (leftist) orthodoxy under the guise of political correctnes­s doesn’t come from liberalism. They come purely from totalitari­anism.

The problem with contempora­ry liberalism isn’t just that it isn’t very liberal, but that it also represents in so many ways everything liberalism opposes.

 ??  ??
 ??  ??
 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States