Baltimore Sun

Ethical framework for animal research

- By David DeGrazia and Tom L. Beauchamp

Change is afoot in the controvers­ial world of animal research, but it needs guidance from an adequate ethical framework.

The EPA just announced it will drasticall­y scale back and eventually eliminate studies testing chemicals on mammals. The Veterans Administra­tion is considerin­g a stop to invasive canine research. Earlier this decade, the NIH ended its funding of biomedical research involving chimpanzee­s.

Do such changes reflect a coherent evolution of policy? Is there a principled framework that can help us decide what types of animal research — or which particular animal studies — are morally justified?

Human research ethics has received guidance from The Belmont Report principles — respect for persons, beneficenc­e and justice — since the late 1970s. Animal research ethics needs a comparably robust touchstone.

For over half a century animal research regulation has followed the “3 Rs,” advanced by William Russell and Rex Burch: replace animal models where feasible, reduce the number of animal subjects to what is statistica­lly required, and refine techniques in order to minimize subjects’ pain and distress.

Although a great advance in animal welfare protection, the 3 Rs are outdated. An adequate framework would be responsive to five developmen­ts spanning recent decades: growing public concerns about animal welfare, as reflected in rising interest in meatless food options and the proliferat­ion of animal protection groups; advances in the scientific study of animals’ cognition and behavior, which has illuminate­d their mental complexity and increased respect for them; the emergence and maturation of animal ethics as a scholarly discipline; growing concerns among scientists about poor translatio­n from successful animal studies of medicines to effective use in humans; and advances in the science of alternativ­es to animal research.

Sixty years after publicatio­n of Russell and Burch’s seminal work, the 3 Rs are conspicuou­sly incomplete. They lack any method for determinin­g whether a proposed animal study is worth conducting in light of its prospect of social benefit along with its costs and risks. They also lack a comprehens­ive program of animal welfare protection, including an upper limit on how much harm animals may endure and an expectatio­n to meet their basic needs.

In light of the aforementi­oned developmen­ts and the 3 Rs’ inadequacy as an ethical framework, it is unsurprisi­ng that public support for animal research in the U.S. has declined in recent years — now hovering at about 50% acceptance.

The public is divided. Moreover, many believe that the biomedical-research and animal-protection communitie­s have hopelessly incompatib­le perspectiv­es. The former, for the most part, considers animal research a necessary component of biomedical progress and judges that harms imposed on animals in research are ethically defensible. The latter is more skeptical about both the benefits of animal research and the justificat­ion of using animals in ways that seriously harm them. Given the perception of an unbridgeab­le gulf dividing these perspectiv­es, one might think that disagreeme­nts about animal research ethics inevitably reduce to a contest of political power.

We disagree. Reasonable representa­tives of the biomedical research community, the animal protection community and the public at large can agree on two core values underlying animal research ethics: social benefit, the appropriat­e end of animal research; and animal welfare, which limits permissibl­e means to pursuing this end.

From this common ground, and mindful of the need for a more robust guide than the 3 Rs, we have developed an ethical framework of six principles for animal research — three principles of social benefit and three of animal welfare — in a book forthcomin­g with Oxford University Press this fall. Following our proposal are commentari­es by seven eminent scholars representi­ng such fields as primatolog­y, veterinary medicine, comparativ­e psychology, law and ethics. Despite these scholars’ willingnes­s to criticize various aspects of our framework, all agree that its adoption would entail significan­t progress in animal research ethics.

Implementa­tion of the principles of social benefit — which together comprise a rigorous cost-benefit standard — would spur more successful translatio­n from animal studies to clinical use while eliminatin­g studies that are poorly designed, insufficie­ntly important or overly harmful. Implementa­tion of the principles of animal welfare would promote decent lives for animal subjects, an appropriat­e goal considerin­g that their involvemen­t is nonconsens­ual and rarely therapeuti­c for them. The terms of the new framework would encourage constructi­ve communicat­ion between the animal research community and animal protection community while affording the public stronger grounds for embracing the animal research enterprise. Finally, the framework would allow policy changes in animal research to proceed in a principled manner.

 ?? ABEL URIBE/CHICAGO TRIBUNE ?? University of Chicago neurobiolo­gy professor Peggy Mason tends to the rats in her lab.
ABEL URIBE/CHICAGO TRIBUNE University of Chicago neurobiolo­gy professor Peggy Mason tends to the rats in her lab.

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States