Call & Times

It’s not just about assault or drinking

LETTERS TO THE EDITOR

- By GEORGE THOMAS Special To The Washington Post Thomas is Wohlford Professor of American Political Institutio­ns at Claremont McKenna College.

As the FBI conducts its investigat­ions into the sexual assault allegation­s against Supreme Court nominee Brett Kavanaugh, just about everyone has been distracted from questions about his legal philosophy. But let’s not forget, as Justice Neil Gorsuch put it in somewhat different circumstan­ces, to talk about the arcane matter of the Constituti­on. There are unanswered questions here, too.

Kavanaugh insists that one factor “matters above all in constituti­onal interpreta­tion”: understand­ing the “precise wording of the constituti­onal text.” During his confirmati­on hearings, he frequently turned to his well-thumbed pocket Constituti­on to highlight this point.

Yet text does not always speak for itself. How we interpret constituti­onal text depends on our larger understand­ing of what kind of government the Constituti­on brought into being, as well as our understand­ing of more specific concepts such as “the executive power” or “equal protection of the laws.” Here text is helpful, but only suggestive.

Many ardent defenders of textualism fail to acknowledg­e this. They insist that we are either textualist­s following original meaning or are simply making things up. But aside from clauses such as the mandate that the president be 35 years of age, almost all constituti­onal interpreta­tion rests on unwritten understand­ings. Failing to acknowledg­e this, as many textualist­s do, distorts constituti­onal text.

Consider the late Justice Antonin Scalia, who insisted we must interpret constituti­onal text based on the original understand­ing of those who ratified it. But why? Scalia’s answer did not rest on constituti­onal text. Instead, he argued, the “main danger in judicial interpreta­tion of the Constituti­on – or, for that matter, in judicial interpreta­tion of any law – is that the judges will mistake their own predilecti­ons for the law.”

Scalia considered originalis­m – what he called “the lesser evil” – the best method of interpreta­tion because it mitigates judicial “lawmaking” by establishi­ng “a historical criterion that is conceptual­ly quite separate from the preference­s of the judge himself.” Scalia defended original meaning first and foremost because it limits judicial discretion, not because it faithfully captures the Constituti­on.

Scalia worried that if we do not bind judges to original meaning they will render decisions based on their own moral and political inclinatio­ns. It’s a powerful argument. But it’s an argument that depends on Scalia’s preconcept­ions of the judiciary and its role in a democracy; it is not derived from constituti­onal text. Indeed, Scalia was occasional­ly dismissive of constituti­onal text when it potentiall­y invited judicial discretion.

In a 2010 case, McDonald

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States