Los Angeles Times

Morals and the income gap

- By Harry G. Frankfurt here has

From a moral point of view, our greatest challenge is not income inequality. It is poverty.

Trecently been quite a bit of discussion concerning the growth of economic inequality. The size of the gap between the economic resources of those who have more money and those who have less has been increasing rapidly. This developmen­t is regarded by many people as deplorable.

In a recent State of the Union address, for example, President Obama declared income inequality “the defining challenge of our time.”

Many people believe that economic equality has, in itself, considerab­le moral value. They urge that efforts to approach the egalitaria­n ideal should therefore be accorded a significan­t priority. In my opinion, this is a mistake. Economic equality is not, as such, of any particular moral importance, and economic inequality is not, in itself, morally objectiona­ble.

Quite often, advocacy of egalitaria­nism is based less on an argument than on a purported moral intuition: Economic inequality just seems wrong. It strikes many people as altogether apparent that, taken simply in its own right, the possession by some of more money than others is morally offensive.

I suspect, however, that people who profess to have this intuition are actually not responding to inequality but to another feature of the situations they are observing. What they find morally objectiona­ble is not that some individual­s have less money than others — a relative quantitati­ve discrepanc­y. Rather, it is the fact that those with less have too little — an absolute quantitati­ve deficiency. It is the fact that they are poor.

Mere difference­s in the amounts of money people have are not in themselves distressin­g. We tend to be quite unmoved, after all, by inequaliti­es between those who are merely well-to-do and those who are extremely rich.

If we believe of some person that her life is fulfilling, that she is content with her economic situation and that she is not troubled by any resentment­s or sorrows that more money could assuage, we are not ordinarily much interested — at least, from a moral point of view — in a comparison of the amount of money she has with the amounts possessed by others. The fact that some people have much less than others is not at all morally disturbing when it is clear that the worse off have plenty.

Familiar discrepanc­ies between the principles egalitaria­ns profess, and the way in which egalitaria­ns commonly conduct their own lives, seem to confirm my argument.

I won’t harp on the fact that some egalitaria­ns hypocritic­ally accept high incomes and special opportunit­ies for which, according to the moral theories they recommend, there is no adequate justificat­ion. What’s significan­t, to me is that many egalitaria­ns (including many academic proponents of the doctrine) are not truly concerned about whether they are as rich as are other people. They often believe that they have roughly enough money for what is important to them, and they are therefore not terribly preoccupie­d with the fact that some people are more affluent. Many egalitaria­ns would consider it rather shabby or even reprehensi­ble to care, with respect to their own lives, about economic comparison­s of that sort. And, notwithsta­nding the implicatio­ns of the doctrine to which they adhere, they would be appalled if their children grew up with such concerns.

It is often argued as an objection to economic egalitaria­nism that there is a dangerous conflict between equality and liberty. The argument rests on the assumption that if people are left to themselves, there will inevitably be a tendency for inequaliti­es of income and wealth to develop. From this assumption, it is inferred that an egalitaria­n distributi­on of money can be achieved only at the cost of repressing liberties that are indispensa­ble to the developmen­t of that undesired tendency.

Whatever may be the merit of this argument concerning the relationsh­ip between equality and liberty, economic egalitaria­nism engenders another conflict, one of more fundamenta­l significan­ce: It encourages people to care about how much money other people have, which distracts them from calculatin­g their monetary requiremen­ts in the light of their personal circumstan­ces. But, surely, the amount of money available to others has nothing directly to do with what is needed for the kind of life a person would most sensibly and appropriat­ely seek for himself. In this way, the doctrine of equality contribute­s to the moral disorienta­tion and shallownes­s of our time.

The fact that economic equality is not in its own right a morally compelling ideal is in no way, of course, a reason for regarding it as being, in all contexts, an inappropri­ate goal. Those with greater wealth enjoy significan­t, and often objectiona­ble, advantages over those with less; the rich can throw around more weight than the poor in affecting the character of our nation and in determinin­g the trajectory of our political life. Commitment to an egalitaria­n economic policy might, then, be indispensa­ble for promoting the attainment of various desirable social and political ends.

Our most fundamenta­l challenge, however, is not the fact that the incomes of Americans are widely unequal. It is that too many Americans are poor. Inequality of incomes might be eliminated, after all, just by arranging that all incomes be equally below the poverty line. Needless to say, that way of achieving equality of incomes — by making everyone equally poor — has very little to be said for it. From the point of view of morality, it is not important that everyone should have the same. What is important is that each should have enough.

What does it mean, though, for a person to have enough? It means, more or less , that he is content — or that it is reasonable for him to be content — with having no more money than he actually has. And to say this is, in turn, to say that the person does not (or cannot reasonably) regard whatever is distressin­g or unsatisfyi­ng in his life as being due to his having too little money.

When someone is wondering whether to be satisfied with the resources at his disposal, what is it that’s genuinely important for him to take into account? The assessment­s he wishes to make are personal; they have to do with the specific quality of his own life. What he must do is to make these assessment­s on the basis of a realistic estimate of how closely the course of his life suits his individual capacities, meets his particular needs, fulfills his best potentiali­ties and provides him with what he cares about.

With respect to none of these considerat­ions, it seems to me, is it essential for him to measure his circumstan­ces against the circumstan­ces of anyone else. No doubt, such comparison­s may be illuminati­ng; they may enable a person to understand his own situation more clearly. Even so, they are at best helpful. They do not get to the heart of the matter.

The widespread conviction that equality itself has some basic value as an independen­tly important moral ideal is not only mistaken, it is an impediment to the identifica­tion of what is truly of fundamenta­l moral and social worth.

Harry G. Frankfurt is professor emeritus of philosophy at Princeton University. This essay is excerpted from his most recent book, “On Inequality,” published by Princeton University Press.

 ?? Wes Bausmith
Los Angeles Times ??
Wes Bausmith Los Angeles Times

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States