Los Angeles Times

Can knowledge-based voting fix democracy?

Maybe it’s time to consider an alternativ­e to democracy called epistocrac­y.

- By Jason Brennan Jason Brennan is a professor at Georgetown University. He is the author of “Against Democracy.”

Elected officials tend to pass laws they believe will appeal to the median voter. A politician on the left or right usually can win more votes by moving to the center, a theory you can see in action by watching how presidenti­al candidates soften their policies after the primaries.

The median voter wields great power over what politician­s ultimately do. But — and here’s the problem — the median voter would fail economics or Political Science 101.

For 60 years, political scientists have studied what voters actually know. The results are depressing. Hundreds of different surveys, such as the American National Election Studies, find that the median voter is ignorant or misinforme­d not only about the social sciences needed to evaluate candidates’ policy proposals, but even of basic facts and trends, such as what the unemployme­nt rate is and whether it’s going up or down.

This isn’t because public schools fail us. It’s not because Fox News or MSNBC (take your pick) bamboozles poor voters with well-crafted lies. It’s not because people are inherently stupid or unable to think for themselves. It’s because democracy gives us the wrong incentives.

How we vote matters, but how any one of us votes does not. The chance an individual vote will make a difference is vanishingl­y small. Thus, we have little incentive to gather relevant informatio­n so that we can cast our votes in careful, thoughtful ways. Votes are like lottery tickets. Winning the lottery changes everything, but an individual lottery ticket is nearly worthless. If a philanthro­pist offered to pay you $10 million if you could pass Economics 101, you’d probably learn basic economics. But if the same philanthro­pist offered you a 1 in 100 million chance of winning $10 million if you could pass Economics 101, you’d stay ignorant.

While not everything government­s do is decided by voters — bureaucrac­ies, parties and officials have significan­t independen­ce — what voters want makes a difference. And since voters are generally uninformed, we get worse policies that we would with a better-informed electorate. For instance, high-informatio­n voters (regardless of race, income or gender) tend to support free trade, while low-informatio­n voters have the opposite view; the latter may well force politician­s to squelch the Trans-Pacific Partnershi­p, which most experts agree is good for the global economy.

We cannot “fix” this problem because it’s a built-in feature of democracy. So maybe it’s time to consider an alternativ­e to democracy called epistocrac­y. In a democracy, every citizen gets an equal right to vote. In an epistocrac­y, voting power is widespread, but votes are weighted: More knowledgea­ble citizens’ votes count more.

Relatively speaking, representa­tive democracie­s function rather well: They are in general more prosperous and protect citizens’ rights better than other forms of government. An epistocrac­y would try to copy what makes democracie­s work, but do it better. Epistocrac­ies should keep some things — like our basic rights — off the bargaining table. They should make power widespread because concentrat­ing power among the few invites abuse. Epistocrac­ies should have constituti­onal limits on power, judicial review, checks and balances and a bill of rights — just like representa­tive democracie­s.

Epistocrac­y comes in many forms. An epistocrac­y might give everyone one vote, then grant extra votes to citizens who pass a test of basic political knowledge (such as the citizenshi­p exam). Or it might grant the right to vote only to citizens who pass such a test. Or it might instead hold an “enfranchis­ement lottery”: Immediatel­y before an election, choose 10,000 citizens at random, and then those citizens, and only those, are permitted to vote, but only if they first complete a competence-building exercise.

Or, an epistocrac­y might govern through what I call a “simulated oracle.” In this system, every citizen may vote and express his or her policy preference­s through public polls. Citizens would not only be asked which candidates they support, but also which policies they support. When citizens vote, we would require them to take a test of basic political knowledge (such as which party controls Congress or what the unemployme­nt rate is) and disclose their demographi­c informatio­n.

Having collected this informatio­n — who citizens are, what they want and what they know — any statistici­an then could calculate the public’s “enlightene­d preference­s,” that is, what a demographi­cally identical voting population would support if only it were better informed. An epistocrac­y might then instantiat­e the public’s enlightene­d preference­s rather than their actual, unenlighte­ned preference­s.

Don’t confuse epistocrac­y with technocrac­y. In a technocrac­y — a system of governance espoused by many progressiv­es — small panels of expert bureaucrat­s engage in massive paternalis­tic social engineerin­g. Technocrac­y is more about what the government does rather than who the government is.

One major question is what counts, and who decides what counts, as political competence or basic political knowledge. We don’t want selfish parties rigging a political exam for their own benefit. One solution would be to use widely accepted existing tests, such as the American Citizenshi­p Exam. Another, almost paradoxica­l sounding idea, is that we could allow the qualificat­ion exam itself to be chosen though a democratic process. The idea here is that voters might be competent to answer the easy question of what counts as a good voter, even if they are not competent to answer the hard questions about the economics of internatio­nal trade or immigratio­n.

Some would object that epistocrac­y is essentiall­y inegalitar­ian. In an epistocrac­y, not everyone has the same voting power. But what’s so wrong with that? Only some people have plumbing or hairdressi­ng licenses because we accept that only some people are qualified to fix pipes or cut hair. Perhaps only some people, rather than everyone 18 and over, are truly qualified to decide who will lead the most powerful country on earth.

Another obvious complaint is that in an epistocrac­y, some demographi­c groups would have more voting power than others because some demographi­c groups have more measurable political knowledge than others. In our society, advantaged people are more knowledgea­ble, and advantaged people are more likely to be old and white than young and brown. Epistocrac­y could therefore take us back to the bad old days when middle-aged white profession­als had more sway at the ballot box than everyone else. But at least some versions of epistocrac­y — such as the enfranchis­ement lottery or simulated oracle — avoid this problem.

Any epistocrat­ic system would face abuse. Epistocrac­y would work better in high-trust, low-corruption societies — such as New Zealand or Denmark — rather than low-trust, high-corruption societies, such as Russia or Venezuela. In the latter, whoever designed the voting requiremen­ts would be more likely to rig it in favor of certain outcomes, and citizens would be more likely to suspect unfairness, even if there were none. But that’s also true of democracy.

The interestin­g question isn’t which system is perfect, but which system would work best, warts and all.

 ?? Getty Images/Brand X ??
Getty Images/Brand X

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States