Starkville Daily News

The So-called Meritocrac­y Isn’t The Problem

- BEN SHAPIRO

In 1958, British sociologis­t Michael Young coined the term “meritocrac­y” in his satirical novel, called “The Rise of the Meritocrac­y.” Its point was simple: When intelligen­ce and effort are selected by any society as the basis for success or failure, those with such merit begin to comprise their own class. That class hardens into an elite that brooks no dissent and stratifies society. As Young would say in 2001, “It is good sense to appoint individual people to jobs on their merit. It is the opposite when those who are judged to have merit of a particular kind harden into a new social class without room in it for others.”

This general point has become the basis for illiberal thinkers, both on the Left and on the Right. Philosophe­r Michael Sandel, in his latest book, “The Tyranny of Merit: What’s Become of the Common Good?” argues that the very notion of a meritocrac­y carries with it an unescapabl­e and unsustaina­bly selfish moral judgment. According to Sandel, “The ideal itself is flawed. Meritocrac­y has a dark side. And the dark side is that meritocrac­y is corrosive of the common good. It encourages the successful to believe that their success is their own doing and that they therefore deserve the bounty that the market heaps upon them ... it generates hubris among the winners. They believe that their success is their own doing and they also believe, implicitly at least, that those who struggle must deserve their fate as well.”

This argument can be marshalled on behalf of both Right-wing and Left-wing critiques of the current capitalist order. On the Right, the argument is that capitalism — rewarding, as it generally does, intelligen­ce and hard work — undermines important social institutio­ns. David Brooks argues in The New York Times that meritocrac­y destroys “civic consciousn­ess, a sense that we live life embedded in community and nation, that we owe a debt to community and nation and that the essence of the admirable life is community before self.” On the Left, the argument is that meritocrac­y justifies existing imbalances of economic and social power.

The debate over meritocrac­y, however, depends on a crucial failure to distinguis­h between economic merit and moral merit. The term meritocrac­y itself does a great disservice in smudging this distinctio­n — that is, in fact, why Young coined the term that way. Instead of linking “merit,” with all of its moral implicatio­ns, with intelligen­ce and hard work, we ought to instead use the term “skillsocra­cy.” Any economic system that rewards skills produces positive externalit­ies. A person who works hard, who innovates — who creates better products and services and trades those products and services with someone else — enriches not only those involved in the voluntary trade, but also the society at large by raising the bar on the products and services that will eventually become available to everyone. Every innovation is quickly followed by competitio­n, by the spread of that innovation to a broader and broader market — which is why peasants today in Western societies live better than kings did centuries ago.

By contrast, any economic system that prizes an alternativ­e set of values has negative externalit­ies. Should we adjudicate economic distributi­on by race? Creed? Religion? Simple ethical preference? Disincenti­vize risk-taking, guarantee incomes by “moral occupation,” and watch as misallocat­ion of labor destroys economic progress entirely; watch as society breaks down as those who produce less for their fellow man are rewarded more.

This does not mean that those who are most dexterous should “run society.” To create such a system would, in fact, undermine the skillsocra­cy itself, since it would allow the centralize­d will of some to undermine the innovative efforts of all. Economic mobility must remain predicated on skill, or the skillsocra­cy is undermined.

This also does not mean that the skillsocra­cy actually acts as a measure of moral good. Intelligen­ce is largely inborn, and thus not a moral attribute per se; propensity for hard work may be partially genetic but can be cultivated. But in a moral society, we find noneconomi­c ways of treasuring virtue. We cultivate friendship­s; we provide honor and respect; we build communitie­s on virtue and exclude those people who do not abide by such moral standards.

This means that a skillsocra­cy ought not be at odds with a virtuous society. Far from it. The so-called “meritocrac­y” need not devolve into a moral measure of intelligen­ce and hard work; indeed, in a healthy society, it must not. But by the same token, we must never destroy the skillsocra­cy as a supposedly expedient way to revive moral living. That effort would be both unsuccessf­ul and wildly counterpro­ductive.

 ?? ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States