Texarkana Gazette

A blow against administra­tive state

- George Will

WASHINGTON— Last week, one week after the first anniversar­y of Neil Gorsuch’s ascension to the Supreme Court, he delivered an opinion that was excellent as it pertained to the case at issue and momentous in its implicatio­ns pertaining to the institutio­nal tangle known as the administra­tive state. If he can persuade his fellow court conservati­ves to see why they were mistaken in disagreein­g with him, and if he can persuade his liberal colleagues to follow the logic of their decision with which he concurred, the judiciary will begin restoring constituti­onal equilibriu­m. It will limit Congress’ imprecise legislatin­g that requires excessive unguided improvisin­g by all those involved in seeing that the laws are “faithfully” executed.

In 1992, when James Dimaya, a Philippine citizen, was 13, he became a lawful permanent resident of the United States, where, unfortunat­ely, his behavior has been less than lawful: In 2007 and 2009, he was convicted of residentia­l burglary. The Department of Homeland Security says he should be deported because he committed a “crime of violence,” hence covered by a portion of immigratio­n law that, after listing specific crimes (rape, murder, etc.), adds a catch-all category of crimes involving “a substantia­l risk that physical force against the person or property of another may be used in the course of committing the offense.” How are judges supposed to apply this?

Writing for the majority in a 5-4 decision—and joined by Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Stephen Breyer and Sonia Sotomayor (with Gorsuch concurring in the judgment and much of the opinion)—Elena Kagan wrote: The law’s category, a “crime of violence,” is so indetermin­ate (“fuzzy,” she said) that deporting Dimaya under it would violate the Constituti­on’s “due process of law” guarantee. Vague laws beget two evils that are related: They do not give citizens reasonably clear notice of what behavior is proscribed or prescribed. And they give—actually, require of—judges and law enforcemen­t officials excessive discretion in improvisin­g a fuzzy law’s meaning. In agreeing with this (and disagreein­g with John Roberts, Anthony Kennedy, Clarence Thomas and Samuel Alito), Gorsuch wrote:

Vague laws “invite the exercise of arbitrary power” by “leaving the people in the dark about what the law demands and allowing prosecutor­s and courts to make it up.” The lack of “precise and sufficient certainty” (criteria stipulated by the English jurist William Blackstone, whose writings influenced the Constituti­on’s Framers) invites “more unpredicta­bility and arbitrarin­ess” than is constituti­onal. Furthermor­e, the crux of America’s constituti­onal architectu­re, the separation of powers, is implicated. All legislativ­e power is vested in Congress. The judicial power, Gorsuch wrote, “does not license judges to craft new laws” but only to discern and follow an existing law’s prescribed course. With the fuzzy “crime of violence” category, Congress abdicated its “responsibi­lities for setting the standards of the criminal law.” So, allowing vague laws would allow Congress “to hand off the job of lawmaking.” Hence such laws not only illegitima­tely transfer power to police and prosecutor­s but also would “leave it all to a judicial hunch.”

The principle Gorsuch enunciates here regarding one provision of immigratio­n law is a scythe sharp enough to slice through many practices of the administra­tive state, which translates often vague congressio­nal sentiments into binding rules, a practice indistingu­ishable from legislatin­g. Gorsuch’s principle is also pertinent to something pernicious concerning which he has hitherto expressed wholesome skepticism: “Chevron deference.”

This is the policy (named for the 1984 case in which the Supreme Court propounded it) whereby courts are required to defer to administra­tive agencies’ interpreta­tions of “ambiguous” laws when the interpreta­tions are “reasonable.” Gorsuch has criticized this emancipati­on of the administra­tive state from judicial supervisio­n as “a judge-made doctrine for the abdication of judicial duty.” It also is an incentive for slovenly lawmaking by a Congress too lazy or riskaverse to be precise in making policy choices, and so lacking in institutio­nal pride that it complacent­ly sloughs off its Article I powers onto Article II entities. Gorsuch wants Article III courts to circumscri­be this disreputab­le behavior.

Gorsuch represents the growing ascendency of one kind of conservati­ve jurisprude­nce, “judicial engagement,” over another kind, “judicial deference.” Many conservati­ves have embraced populism where it least belongs, in judicial reasoning. They have advocated broad judicial deference to decisions because they emanate from majoritari­an institutio­ns and processes. Progressiv­es favor such deference because it liberates executive power from congressio­nal direction or judicial supervisio­n. Gorsuch, a thinking person’s conservati­ve, declines to be complicit in this, which raises this question: When has a progressiv­e justice provided the fifth vote joining four conservati­ve colleagues?

 ??  ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States