The Sentinel-Record

Losing the argument

- Bradley R. Gitz Arkansas Democrat-Gazette Freelance columnist Bradley R. Gitz, who lives and teaches in Batesville, received his Ph.D. in political science from the University of Illinois.

Those who support some kind of legal access to abortion are going to lose the debate if they keep putting forth dumb arguments like the following:

• Dobbs proves conservati­ves care more about the unborn than the born.

This convenient­ly ignores the primary pro-life premise that the unborn fetus and the born child are both human beings equally entitled to the pursuit of life, liberty, and happiness.

It isn’t so much that the born are subordinat­e in priority to the unborn in such thinking as the unborn are elevated to equal status with the born.

This may be wrong, but it follows logically from the premise.

• Dobbs proves that conservati­ves don’t care about women. Again, it isn’t so much that unborn are given priority over women as that the lives of the unborn are given priority over the preference­s of pregnant women, but even then, consistent with pro-life principles, only up to the point where women’s lives are threatened (thereby permitting abortion only in cases where the actual life of the mother is at risk, and it becomes a choice between saving the life of one or the other).

If the fetus is a human being, then its right to life logically takes precedence over other rights.

• The “legitimacy” of the court has been severely damaged by Dobbs (but somehow wasn’t by Roe).

Legitimacy in politics means the possession of rightful authority, which flows from adherence to law. Nothing in Dobbs suggests that such adherence was lacking—the six members of the court that ruled to overturn Roe were put on the court through the same constituti­onal (“advise and consent”) process as the three judges in the minority; Dobbs was heard in the same fashion as other cases before the court; and both majority and minority issued the traditiona­l opinions laying out the reasons for their positions.

Reduced to its essence, those making the illegitima­cy argument are saying the court is legitimate only if it rules the way they want it to. But if anything, the legitimacy of a court is enhanced when it resists pressure and produces rulings that displease much of the public; were it otherwise, it would be a robed legislatur­e rather than a court.

The loyalty of the justices is to the Constituti­on, not to Gallup polls with respondent­s who have only the haziest notion of the contents of that Constituti­on (indeed, much of our post-Dobbs polling suggests that those most upset over Roe being overturned don’t have a clue as to what it permitted or prohibited).

Public institutio­ns become illegitima­te only when they fail to adhere to the rules dictated by the process of self-government (the law) and/or clearly overstep authority conferred by law. Neither condition was present in Dobbs (if anything, the latter was in what Dobbs overturned, Roe).

• The kind of “original intent” argument relied upon by the majority in Dobbs and by more conservati­ve jurists in general is to be rejected because some of those whose intent is being discerned were slaveowner­s or guilty of some other offense against contempora­ry sensibilit­ies.

What this claim essentiall­y amounts to is a rejection not just of original intent interpreta­tions but of the rule of law itself, since it suggests that the inevitable moral defects of lawmakers renders the laws they pass in a democratic process null and void; we would thus, each of us according to our varied moral sense, be free to pick and choose which laws we would obey and not.

If our highest law of the land is merely a “slaveholde­rs’ Constituti­on,” then that same document also leaves us free to amend it in such a fashion as to remove the effects of the slaveholdi­ng (as many thought had long been done), or, if that proves infeasible, to call for a new constituti­onal convention to undo altogether the mischief done at Philadelph­ia.

Barring such steps, the Constituti­on remains in effect and original intent should continue to dictate court rulings regardless of what we think of James Madison, George Washington and company (or of those who, later, made 27 revisions to their handiwork, including those that abolished slavery, granted women the right to vote, and gave that right to 18-year-olds).

In short, the pro-choice position might be mistaken for various reasons, but it behooves those of us on the other side to at least present their views fairly and accurately, and then explain why they are wrong.

The most important part of this involves articulati­ng a persuasive definition of human life and identifyin­g at what point, if any, during pregnancy it becomes present—if the fetus is merely a tomato, as so much pro-choice rhetoric callously suggests, then there is nothing to debate, because the interests of women are the only interest; but if it is something else (a human life?), then the nature of the debate abruptly changes.

“Reproducti­ve rights” don’t matter if they come at the expense of a human life, and it is therefore necessary for abortion-rights supporters to prove that a 4-month-old fetus in the womb is something other than that.

So when does life begin and why?

If you are unwilling to answer those questions, your opinion on the subject is worthless.

 ?? ??

Newspapers in English

Newspapers from United States